20. One argument against
a semantically based stage-1 was that from the very beginning,
children’s productive multi-word speech
(MLU= 2+) yielded Inflectional plurals {+s} and gerund {+ing}
endings—the first two morphemes to be
acquired according to Brown’s morpho-sequencing list. These
endings were only attached to syntactic categorial
word-classes: e.g., {s} to nouns, {ing} to verbs, etc.
There seemed to be no attempt by the young child to generalize
such inflections onto pure semantic categories.
In other words, if children’s word classes at this stage-1 were
thematic, rather than syntactic innature, we would
expect that specific inflections would be distributed along
semantico-thematic lines: e.g., plural {s}
to agent, gerund {ing} to action words, etc. (Radford 1990,
41). Such findings are not reported in the data.
It was this absence of semantically based grammars which led
discussions about possible a priori innate
grammatical categories, a grammar based on a syntax (without
meaning) rather than a syntax based on semantics
(meaning) (cf. general vs. special nativism). Although
it is indeed correct to suggest that there
seem to be no purely semantically based Inflections at stage-1,
one argument against the conclusion
of the claim, and seemingly in support of a semantically-based
stage-1, would be to suggest that, in fact, most
utterances at this stage are instances of formulaic constructions.
Only at a later stage-2 would we find instances
of real productive inflection—viz., even though on the
surface, inflection appears to be utilized at stage-1,
the surface structure only mimic input driven
phonological patterns.
21. This ‘mixed bag’ of a grammatical
stage is indeed an argument against ‘too-strong-of-claim’
syntactic-based model of early grammar
(assuming that a syntactic version holds as a buttress for
Continuity—we shall take some comfort in it
however due to the fact that this strong claim we take will
be short lived and relegated to the very earliest
of grammatical stages: (=MLU below 2). There is a
caveat here. One argument, however, against interpreting
from no evidence-namely, the observation that no
inflection shows up on argument-themes might be the following:
If our stage-1 were in fact formulaic, and not rule-based,
then there indeed would be no utterance of an improper formulaic
inflection attached to a semantic category simply
because this would not have been available in the phonological
input.
Formula constructions come out of the input in a highly
regular manner—based on high frequency, saliency
and churn out as formulaic un-analyzable chunks. (See 40 for
an account of apparently correct parameterized word
order found at an otherwise non-parameterized stage of acquisition).
22. The argument could run as follows. The fact that
children at stage-1 never produce e.g., the action-
inflection ‘-ing’ to semantically classed action-words
like *up-ing/down-ing/over-ing/on-ing, etc.
merely indicates that such strings are not part of the
available input (particularly note worthy given that
our stage- 1 is semi-formulaic in nature). It will be argued
that the very earliest of stages (stage-1),
addressed herein, is indeed the very earliest of staged developmental
grammar—what may have been even termed a-grammatical
in previous theories (viz., the one word stage (cf. Atkinson,
1992; Radford, 1990; among others). Let it be known
that I am all too ready to acknowledge and agree that language
is indeed built upon pure syntax at our stage-2
of development, (and not on semantics): the classic
evidence for a syntactic-based language at the earliest
stages has been taken from the child’s inflectional
system at work on the basis of grammatical categories. Notwithstanding
early attempts to cast syntactic analyses to early
stages of language, there has been attempts in the child language
acquisition literature to construct a dual model
for stage-1 based on (i) semantico-thematic relations on one
hand, and (ii) categorial syntax on the other.
This hybrid model has been considered as a lexical-thematic
stage-1 of child language acquisition where mere
semantic properties tied together those lexical syntactic categories
void of any functional material (as related to the
functional categories IP & CP). The most fully
articulated version of this hybrid theory could
be found in Radford (1990):

23. The question is then put to us in the following
form:Is there any evidence at the earliest phases of stage-1
(say MLU<2) that the child actually analyzes
strings as a syntactic structure—as opposed to a formulaic
speech-utterance (i) which may be tethered to a variety
of gradient meanings, and (ii) which may reduce
to mere surface-level syntactic phenomena)? In other words,
what may appear on the surface as syntax proper,
may in all actuality simply be a result of the surface formulae
learned and that real tacit syntactic knowledge
is not represented. There seems to be little that hinges on
the possible alternatives:
If, on the one hand, we consider such semi-formula
as syntax proper-making our stage-1 (MLU<2) a
syntactic stage—then so be it. We are then forced to reconciling
our syntactic stage-1 to the one word stage as previously
thought and nothing is lost.
If, on the other hand, a lexical-thematic stage-1
involved itself with bridging this narrowing gap between
formula and syntax—then so be it. The benefits we have
gained by adapting this measure is that
it allows us a nice continuity bridge onto the later phrases
of stage-1 (MLU +2).
24. One interesting
by-product of such a lexical-thematic stage-1 is that it doesn’t
specify Word Order: being traditionally
tied to functional parameterization (see Atkinson, 1992; Tsimpli,
and Galasso, 1999). Coming on the heels of such
semantic-based models of language acquisition, claims have been
made suggesting that the cause of a
semantic stage-1 is due to memory deficits. As part of a Maturational
time-table, the child starts off with
a very limited memory attention span—this memory deficit
(maturational based) triggers the
more ‘robust & primitive’ semantic-lexical level of language
(since the lexical component is more salient) to
kick start productive communication (see Newport’s ‘Less-is-
More Hypothesis’, S. Felix’s non-UG/cognitive approach
to L2 learning, as well as J. Elman’s work in relation
to connectionism. For evolutionary accounts, see Bickerton’s
Proto-language, 1990).
Less-is-More Hypothesis. According
to Newport’s ‘Less-is-More’ Hypothesis, a Radfordian style
maturational time-table—dividing our stage-1 from stage-2—would
be linked to ‘working memory’ deficits: Stage-1
starts with early limited memory and thus can solely rely on
the more primitive and robust rote-learned
and formulaic structures. (One needn’t say that all possible
structures at stage-1 are rote or formula—let it
suffice to say that the flavor of the stage suggests little
if any evidence for ‘true- rule’ formations
or parameterizations, citing stage-1 variant Word Orders and
null INFLections). This handicap of low memory actually
works as an advantage for the child in that it serves to constrain
the perceived input to basic degree-0 SV(X)
structures—the structures are ready-made by the lower-level
cognitive processes and made available to the stage-1
child. Lower-level memory seeks out idiomatic lexical-based
categories or lexical based morphemes as opposed to functional,
syntactic based morphemes/categories
(termed ‘l’-morphemes’ vs. ‘f’-morphemes respectively by Pesetsky
(1995) as understood in Distributional Morphology
(see §50). (N.B. Felix (1981) as well as Krashen claim that
it is precisely this over-production of the cognitive
apparatus/high memory that makes second language
learning so fraught with difficulty—having to ‘learn’
language overtly instead of naturally ‘acquiring’ it in a
natural setting.)
25. We
can better frame arguments that claim for a cognitive/memory
dependence for language acquisition by addressing
the very nature of syntax. First, syntax requires much more
in the way of computational memory. (Or perhaps
the question is better framed conversely—viz., more memory forces
the computation to reorganize itself
by way of syntax.) The emergence of syntax coincides with the
onset of higher (quantity) amounts of language material—i.e.,
a higher number of memorized words/strings leading to
longer and a richer complexity of sentences, etc. For instance,
Degree-zero structures (say, basic SV sentences,
order irrelevant) come at the expense of lower memorizations,
while, et vice versa, Degree-1 structures, (embeddings,
binding, recursiveness) come at a much higher cost with regards
to memorization. Why is that? Well,
in one manner of speaking the reason is self serving: simply
due to the fact that in order to have a degree-1
sentence, the empirical (maturational) data dictates that a
child must have, at some prior time, gone through
a degree-0 stage, a process that mirrors memorization capacity.
But more to the point, the reason for this mental/computational
juggling has to do with how our brains go about making
the most out of our limited memory capacity. The very nature
of these high amounts of material forces a
shift in how the brain can process (parse) the material. It
is believed in the neuro- linguistic community
that the shift here—both in the quantity and quality of language—triggers
the already over burdened process of rote-learning
and memorization to be lifted, triggering the share of burden
to be replaced by rule-based processes (variables,
categories, etc.). Such rule-based learning frees up space in
the lexical component of the brain (say, the list
of words stored) and allows new routes to be mapped. In
other words, such a huge volume of material forces new
ways of organizing the input (hence,
categorization). In sum, the two-prong development as sketched
out above might proceed as follows:
(i) At the Micro-Development level (stage-1)
the data stream is reduced for the child in terms of its
cognitive saliency: (the output data is not
changed, rather it’s the intervening deficiency of the
child’smental processing that overall affects that data).
The child, working with a primary memory ‘tool-kit’, allows
a small subset-a of language input, this in turn allows
the child to ultimately deal with less dataenabling rote-learning
to take place. (N.B. It is generally acknowledged that
any memory deficit or trauma resulting in language attrition
would first affect the more abstract levels of language/syntax).
(ii) At the Macro-Development level (Stage-2)
the data stream is affected by the upsurge in memorization
that in turn expands what becomes salient for the child.
Perhaps having to do with the triggering of hidden units
at the end of stage-1, the child now is in a position
of capably taking the data and applying paradigmatic structures—all
which lead to formal (stage-2) grammar. Thus, Macro development
makes available more memory which in turn spawns new ways
of handling the material—the initial process of stage-1
rote association and memory is no longer adequate and
syntax proper emerges as a way of handling both the quantity
and quality of this newfound material.
|
26. What syntax allows the brain to do is categorize and
form analogies based on the vast amount of input, rather
than to memorize and store all input as meaningful chunks (with
an associative sound-to-meaning relationship imposed).
This results ultimately in a finite array of neuro-linguistic
networks in the brain. Hence, in a basic input-output
model—similar to what we understand to be happening in behaviorist
stimulus and response associative models—quantity
of input equates to quality of brain processing. As is
evident, the classic enigma (chicken and the egg scenario)
remains: Is it this newly wired brain which now seeks
out the formations of paradigms and variable rules that is responsible
for the quantum leap of quality of language,
or is it this quality leap in language that somehow drives the
changes in the brain? This is tantamount to the
classic Nature vs. Nurture debate. My hunch here is that (i)
the nature of the raw Data as it is (ii)
tied to cognitive processing may be the driving force behind
any structural changes that occur in the brain—in
other words, language changed the brain and not the other way
around. (It may ultimately be impossible to separate
the one from the other). But this is only a hunch, and again,
it reduces to the same catch-22 scenario
(if it is the data that is the driving force behind the change,
how do we account for a maturational protracted development,
and secondly, surely, how the brain handles and processes
the data must be part of the equation for any theory that attempts
to account for developmental stages of
language). In a certain sense, Newport’s ‘less-is-more’ hypothesis
simply restates this same paradox. Regarding
architecture and the nature vs. nurture debate, clearly all
linguists suppose now that some connection must be
made between genes and environment Thus, a two-staged
development follows:
(i) Stage-1 comes with low-level memory with strong
correlates to semantics and rote-learning. As a consequence,
one-to-one sound-to-meaning correspondence ensues explained
by more prosaic economic constraints placed on cognition
(ii) Stage-2 comes with increased memory that (for reasons
having to do with processes of parsing, etc.) triggers
high level categorization and syntax. One-to-many/many-to-one
relations are evoked triggering a highly rich paradigmatic
grammar.
|
27. Radford (2001) more recently has gone on the record
as saying that the Language Faculty specifies a
universal set of features—namely, that a child acquiring language
has to learn which subset of these features
are assembled into the lexical items as +universal (all other
features awaiting parameterization via a maturational
timetable). The problem for the child is assembling the features
into lexical items. To a certain degree, the
child needs to build-up lexical items feature at a time (see
Clahsen’s Lexical Learning Hypothesis). Thus, the
issue for Radford is that there are innate architectural principles—loosely
referred to as an Innate Grammar Construction Algorithm—which
determine how lexical items project into syntactic
structures. This begs the following question: How much of this
initial learning deficit cited for our lexical stage-1
is owed to the child’s protracted language development being
exclusively tied to a maturational based
low-scope cognitive template—a potentially semantic based template
upon which later formal abstract categories (such
as functional categories) can be mapped? It is clear at least
that more abstract functional categories come
on-line later in the course of development.
28. General vs. Special Nativism. This
is a nice place to pause and examine the role that our
lower-scope cognitive processes might play in deciphering
between Stage-1 vs. stage-2 grammar. In brief,
there are two schools of thinking on this, both of which could
maintain general ties to a Chomskyan paradigm. One
school takes an evolutionary stance (Pinker & Bloom) and
basically claims that lexical learning leading
to grammaticalization is heavily based on what are preexisting
cognitive constraints (much in the manner of former
Piagetian models of language development). Such linguists would
disagree with the notion that a special module in
the brain must exist in order for language to manifest. Recall,
Chomsky in his strongest claims suggests that the
Language Faculty (LF) is an independent autonomous organ
found somewhere in the mind/brain (similar to say
the liver or the stomach) and that this LF organ shares
very little in the way of general cognitive processes—a
language module all to its own and without
common lineages to other regions or modules of the brain.
This notion is referred to in the language acquisition
literature as a Double Disassociation Hypothesis (disassociation
between formal language and cognition) (see Smith
and Tsimpli for some discussion). The second anti-Neo-Darwinian
position suggests that a special module
in the brain is required for language, and that language learning
can be accounted for by reduced/non-cognitive
means.
29. Regarding the
debate over General vs. Special Nativism, it is
still unclear how the debate should be viewed. Much
of the argument quickly degenerates into the classic aforementioned
‘chicken-and-the- egg’ dilemma of being circular
in nature: e.g., (i) The Special Nativist claims that the child
first needs syntax to uncover the underlying
semantics (syntactic-bootstrapping), while (ii) The General
nativist insures that in order to properly
construct a syntax category in the first place, general properties
of (inherent) cognitive-semantics must be
observed (semantic-bootstrapping). (Interesting, Chomsky’s
most recent work on Minimalism suggest that there
may be economical constraints on language
processing (from out of Logical Form). While it is still
unclear how to interpret the wide range of claims
on the minimalist table, and Chomsky himself often remains agnostic
at these levels of inquiry, such economic
constraints could be interpreted as indeed not pertaining to
consideration of pure syntax, and rather adhering
to more cognitive levels of processing: e.g., Minimalist notions
of shortest move, minimal amount of rules, and to
a certain degree, the objective essence behind the (PF) phonological
form of language as versus the (LF) logic
form, etc.). On one hand however, it seems to me that a dualist
approach to acquisition (as presented
herein) would initially favor a first order semantic-bootstrapping
view, given that semantics seem to play an essential
role in language acquisition early on before the onset
of syntax. (There is no conclusion drawn here, as nothing
argued in this paper hinges on that debate).
30.
Why—I don’t need any ‘rules’ to see this tree. My eyes
work just fine. That is, insofar as there exists a single
tree. How is it that my ‘tree’ gets destroyed once I move
my head ever so slightly to the east and fall into view
of a second tree? The mystery of it all lies somewhere in
the dismantling, between a single torn branch
of lifted foliage, that forces the rule—for how was I ever
to know that this second tree was indeed a tree after all?
|
Well, the above passage makes for a nice analogy,
but it merits a closer look. When I look at this cup of
coffee in front of me, reach out for it, anddrink its
contents, it certainly appears to me that I do little more
than what my own cognitive abilities lets me achieve—I
don’t perform any ‘abstract rule’ formulations,
procedures as such, although, I do agree that one could possibly
uncover all of the aforementioned procedural
content coming together such as e.g., Gestalt psychology, visual
cortex processing, contextual/meta-linguistic
background of say [+liquid] => drink => mouth, along with
muscle motor coordination that allows me to
see into space reaching and holding the cup without breaking
the glass (etc.). In face of all this possible
theory, it remains somewhat natural for me to maintain the idea
that when I see a tree, I just see a tree
(period). But much has come out of Gestalt theory in the past
(being somewhat reframed here in the present context
of connectionism) that suggests there may be something
to this very natural notion of just seeing after all.
Gestalt theory on perception states that there are
first-order perceptions in which, say, a child might see
a line or a slope in a strict iconic representation of
the visual field. No rules apply—and there is a strict
Stimulus and Response (S&R) equation involved.
Regarding language acquisition, this first-order representation
could be illustrated by the early onset of vowel
recognition (i.e., environmental sound)—and not sound as filtered
through assimilation processes, etc. (as seen in
the u-shaped model below). At a later stage of perception, second-order
perceptions allow the child to break iconic
mappings and allow lines, slopes, etc. to begin to be seen (with
less vividness) as e.g., a chair—now, a larger,
somewhat more generic unit, which embodies the lower level
visual stimuli. It seems to be the case that the role of
second-order perceptions is to pull and frame larger aspects
of Objects and Events—in linguistic terms, forming Nouns (out
of the former) and Verbs (out of the latter). So
regarding language, we should be clear that by the time a child
reaches the very first stages of language development—where
a child is said to begin producing single word utterances—s/he
has already moved from the first-order perceptual
field into a second-order field. So, the idea that children
may have some means to rules, perhaps bootstrapped
from Gestalt psychology (the General Nativist Position)
may not be totally implausible. However, and more to our point,
Newport’s ‘Less-is-More’ hypothesis just as
well could be interpreted to fit Gestalt findings: when memory/cognitive
capacity is low, children see in a fixed iconic manner,
and when memory/cognitive capacity increases, the child
reorganized the visual field and must begin
to classify according to class—e.g., the child sees a chair
(second-order) as opposed to a chaotic string
of lines and slopes, etc. So, roughly, the theme throughout
holds—memory/cognitive capacity drives computational
order. One way though to save our nice analogy is
by pinning it down (to a narrow application) to issues surrounding
Lexical S&R behaviorism vs. Functional
rule-based grammar. Surely, the spirit of the analogy is well
taken. Yes, iff (if and only if) I ever saw one tree,
I could adhere and maintain an exclusive iconic S&R process;
it is when I look and see another tree that
I must compare notes and begin to re-organize both visual trees
into a class of ‘Tree’ (using Plato’s terminology).
Again, Newport’s theme above holds in that too much information,
in this case the second tree, forces an adjustment
in the computation—corresponding to our data drive axiom.
In other words, on one basic and primitive level (order-1),
visual transmission is nothing more than
sensory input directly stimulating the sensory cortex). However,
at a more abstract and functional level (order-2),
perception is not fully determined by sensory input, but is
dependent on intervening processes of Gestalt psychology.
Hence, a dual mechanism account likewise credits a purely cognitive
behavior such as vision as having two distinct modes
of processing—(i) Bottom-up sensory-driven Transmission
and (ii) Top down context-driven Perception.
These two approaches could nicely map onto our analogous
dichotomy between Skinner and S&R style learning
vs. Chomsky’s rule-based symbolic style learning. So,
our emerging linguistic schism separating Derivational morphological
processes from Inflectional processes may not be a
schism relegated to language per se, but may actually
be operative in separating other lower-level
cognitive procedures as well.
Discontinuity: A Lexical-Thematic stage-1
31. It is now widely reported in the literature that
children generally go through a stage during which they
optionally project Functional Categories: e.g., Determiner
Phrases (DP), Finite Main Verb Phrases which mark
Tense (TP), Infinitive and Agreement markings such as infinitive-‘to’
(IP), and 3person/present /singular {s} (AgrP)
(respectively). Wexler (1994) refers to this stage as the Optional
Infinitive stage. In more general terms regarding
Inflection, Wexler’s ‘Optional Infinitive’ stage has recently
been more accurately characterized as an ‘Optional
Inflection’ stage (see Radford & Galasso 1998). More
importantly, a picture seems to emerge in the
investigation of early child speech that shows an even earlier
stage of development—a stage in which the overall
deficit well exceeds any notion of Infinitive/Inflectional
Optionality. Mainly speaking, there seems to exist a stage-1
in the course of child language acquisition —briefly
peaking at around two years of age with MLUw well below 2.5
and then quickly falling off—which indicates
‘No Inflection’ whatsoever. What might have been too hastily
claimed a stage-1 in Wexler’s terms, must now be
relegated to a stage-2 in Radford & Galasso’s terms. It
so happens that Wexler has been a leading proponent
of maturational-based theories of language acquisition, so
supporting arguments for Continuity based on
the optionality data as presented by Wexler and his
colleges don’t get a fair play. Likewise interpretations
regarding our own work here would most certainly
solicit continuity in getting at fair play—that is, however,
only if it were the case that Wexler’s stage-1 indeed
simply equated to our stage-1. As it turns out, it doesn’t.
Our stage-1 is much more systematically avoid of
functional material. In other words, Wexler’s OI-model doesn’t
offer us a solid, foul-proof discontinuity
model. By definition, ‘optionality’ suggest that the child has
some working tacit competence of the adult target
grammar—it may only be that the performance level or mastery
of such competence is lacking. Certainly, this is
a far cry from any possible notion of a ‘strong discontinuity’
theory.
32. One Continuity argument could run as follows. Since,
the child at the earliest of conceivable syntactic
stages is already marking Inflection (albeit optionally),
then there is no justifiable reason to assume (even
as the null hypothesis) that child’s grammar is Discontinuous
with the adult target grammar. (In this sense, the
dual mechanism apparatus has established itself from the get-go,
and thus, no child-to-adult discontinuity
has to be assumed). The differences found between the child’s
grammar and adult target grammar would not
be significantly real, in developmental language terms, and
could be readily accounted for by a variety of superficial
means—such as e.g., saliency conditions, morphological feature
spell-out conditions, parameter miss-settings, phonological
complexity and general immature cognitive factors
bringing about the memory deficits of such non-salient
phonological features. Having said this, a very
different scenario emerges if indeed our stage-1 is a stage
that precedes optionality by showing ‘no inflection’
whatsoever. In such a scenario, a discontinuity hypothesis now
seems to emerge as the null hypothesis, as
previously cited above, yielding to highly universal biological
considerations. My own data (a syntactically-coded
naturalistic corpus of well over 10,000 analyzable utterances)
presented in the following sections, taken
from Radford & Galasso (1998) & Galasso (1999), demonstrate
this two- prong stage of acquisition, the consequence
of which will buttress our calls for Discontinuity. (N.B. It
goes without saying that by postulating a ‘dual
mechanism model’ for adult language systems, any
working theory claiming a stage in which a child starts-off
with a truncated ‘single model’ (for stage-1) would
be tantamount to discontinuity).
The Inflection {‘s’}
33. In examining the ‘portmonteau’-morpheme {s}, the data
provide (prima facie) evidence of some
relation between the acquisition of Possessive {‘s} and the
Third person singular {s}. At our stage-1,
there is no evidence of the inflectional marker across the board,
it is only with the onset of our so labeled ‘Stage-2’
(from age 3,2 onward) that we begin to see Wexler’s notion of
optionality kick-in. The table 3 below shows the
relative frequency of use of Poss(essive) {‘s} and 3Psing {s}
in obligatory contexts before and after age
3;2:
Table 3
Occurrence of Inflection {s}
in Obligatory Contexts
Age |
3SgPres
{s} |
Poss
{‘s} |
2;3-3;1 |
0/69
(0%) |
0/118
(0%) |
3;2-3;6 |
72/168
(43%) |
14/60
(23%) |
Token sentence examples of the two-staged data are
presented below (respectively):
a). That Mommy car (2;6). No Daddy plane
(2;8), Where Daddy bike?
Batman (2;11 in reply to ‘Whose it is’). It Daddy
bike. No Baby bike (3;0).
b). Daddy’s turn (3;2). It’s the man’s
paper (3;4). It’s big boy Nicolas’s.
It’s Tony’s. What’s the girl’s name? Where
is Zoe’s bottle? (3;6).
c). Baby have bottle (2;8). No Daddy have
Babar (2;9).
The car go (2;11) The other one work (3;0).
Here come baby (3;1)
d). Yes, this works. This car works. My
leg hurts. It rains He comes (3;1-3;2).Interestingly,
the data above suggest a potential parallel between the
acquisition of third person singular {s} and possessive
{‘s} (see Radford & Galasso for discussion). |
34. But more importantly, they also suggest that whatever
discontinuity is at work in the child’s grammar, it
seems to manifest across the board in a systematic way. In other
words, the lack of inflection here is not categorical
specific, but rather is realized across categories affecting
both DP and IP alike. It seems that Poss and 3PS
{s} at our stage-1 both reflect general catastrophic
agreement failure. Certainly, any notion of a real
child-to-adult discontinuity would want to be expressed in such
absolute terms—as opposed to any Optional-based theory
which might be corned into spinning arguments from what on the
surface would appear as mere non-mastery and under-specification
of Continuity into arguments for real Discontinuity.
As was expressed above, both deficits could be captured by a
lack of Agreement—a functional property of adult
grammar. Consider then the phrase structure discontinuity of
the two stages below:
Agreement Structure
Stage-1: [ IP Mummy [I -agr
0] car]
Stage-2: [IP Daddy [+agr ‘s] turn]
|
35. It is argued herein that both possessive {‘s} and
third person {s} are reflexes of an agreement relation
between an inflectional head and its specifier-and any omission
reflects an agreement failure. The specific issue
at hand here is that only an absolute omission stage-as seen
with our stage-1—would provide support for true discontinuity.
Any optionality here, e.g., [+/- agr] would play directly into
the hands of Continuity theories with the mere additional
disclaimer that the adult target grammar has indeed been
acquired, but simply not mastered. (See Wexler & Schütze
(1996) for treatments of under-specification of Agr
as would be encountered in our stage-2 data).
Possessors
36. In a similar vain, we find additional support for
a non-target grammar in the wake of data showing Case
errors e.g., with possessors (enter alia). The assumption
that children’s possessive structures may be initially
(i) non-specified, and then later (ii) (optionally) underspecified
with respect to agreement also accounts for the wide
array of case errors where children (at stage-1) use the default
case of objective possessor (me) and only
later come to acquire the target Case of possessor (my),
etc. The use of objective possessors e.g.,
(me) has been reported for Dutch by Hoekstra & Jordens
(1994), but not for English. If we look at the earliest
first person singular possessor structures produced in the data,
we find that objective me possessors predominate
at ages 2;6-2;8, and that Genitive possessors (prenominal my
and pronominal mine) are initially infrequent
(with no cases reported for the use of nominative I for
possessor):
Table 4 Occurrence of First Person Singular Possessors
Age |
Objective
“Me” |
Genitive
“My/Mine” |
2:6-2:8 |
53/55
(96%) |
2/55
(4%) |
2;9 |
11/25
(44%) |
14/25
(56%) |
2;10 |
4/14
(29%) |
10/14
(71%) |
2;11 |
5/24
(21%) |
19/24
(79%) |
3;0 |
4/54
(7%) |
50/54
(93%) |
3;1-3;6 |
6/231
(3%) |
225/231
(97%) |
a). That me car. Have me shoe. Me and Daddy
(=Mine and Daddy’s). Where me car? I want me
bottle. (2;6-2;8)
b). I want me duck. That me chair. Where
me car? No me, Daddy (= It isn’t mine, daddy)
Me pasta, Mine pasta. My pasta. It
my key. It my (=It’s mine). No book my
(=It’s not my book, showing head final construct)
c). It is my t.v. Where is my book? Where
is my ball? Don’t touch my bike. I want
my key. It’s my money. (3;0)
|
37. In terms of the analysis
outlined above, the data seem to suggest that the possessive
structures produced early on (=stage-1) are
predominately not specified for possessor-agreement, with agreement
gradually being specific more and more frequently
(until it exceeds 90% mastery at age 3;0). While it is true
that we can’t argue here for absolute Non-agreement
of Case at stage-1 (whereas for the earliest file, age 2;6,
we get at least two examples of correct my),
this contrast in acquisition—as compared to what we
observed earlier regarding the agreement of the morphological
inflection {s}—may be a residual effect of the
two types of agreement involved: its seems to be the case that
true morphological inflection should be the
benchmark of agreement and not lexical equivalents e.g., prenominal/pronominal
my/mine (respectively)
due to the fact that it is always more difficult to tease
apart lexical form functional underlying structure
and determine if a lexical item is being properly projected
as a functional category, or if merely the
lexical ‘shell’ is simply phonologically produced ‘rote- learned’.
(Also see §50ff regarding such distinctions
placed between the two features as understood in Distributional
Morphology). The above examples could be expressed
by the same type of Phrase structure presented below:
Agreement Structure
38. It could be argued that for our stage-1, ‘adult target’
agreement (acting as a functional and formal feature
of language) is set to the default via a [-agr] setting
and so renders the possessor case objective. The
close to 100% omission of adult-like agreement provides
additional support for a discontinuity theory
between child and adult grammars.
Word
Order
39 One initial assertion that can be made regarding the
possible early insensitivity of verbs towards their
appropriate position within a sentence has come from early
MLU data. For instance, many naturalistic studies
of early language development suggest that rather than generating
structure via abstract g rammatical
generalizations, children may actually be tethering their grammars
to individual lexical items with respect to
functional elements auxiliaries (Kuczaj & Maratsos, 1993,
Pine & Lieven, 1997); determiners
(Pine & Lieven, 1997) and pronouns (Pine & Baldwin,
1997). Data on early verb/argument structure
(see Radford 1990: pp. 213-17 for stage-1 examples) suggest
that early MLU verb classes may not adhere
to appropriate SVO argument structure in the sense that target
transitive verbs take obligatory object arguments.
Radford cites very early two-word structures of the I/(me)
want, Her hit, type where the direct
objects required presence in adult speech go missing. Such deficits
might suggest the children’s initial knowledge
of verb-argument structure to be developed around individual
verbs (and not verb type). In addition, semantic
over-extensions of Intransitive verbs of the ‘Me sleeped
teddy’ type (=sleeped, slept>put to
bed) may likewise show over-extensions on an individual verb
basis (Tomasello, 1992), or individual frame-basis
(Braine, 1976), but show little evidence that the extension
carries over to the entire verb class. In
view of these data, it remains questionable whether or not children’s
very earliest MLU staged grammar operates
with abstract, rule-based representations at all—e.g., [+/-]
Verb Transitivity. More
specific to English SV(X) word order, some questions regarding
rule-based word order parameterization for
early MLU speech have been formulated. Atkinson (1992) (following
the work of Susan Goldin-Meadow with deaf
children and ‘Home Sign’) suggests that there may be no
theoretical reason to stipulate for a correct target word
order at, say, a pre-parameterized stage of development.
If children have an inherent abstract understanding of predicate-argument
structure (cf. Valian, 1991), they should
then be able to understand the differences between the subject
and object of a transitive verb and how to
apply this to word order.
40 Although traditional naturalistic studies have typically
shown that correct SVO word order usually
appears early on in the data (Brown, Cazden, and Bellugi-Klima
(1968), Bloom, 1970; Brown, 1973; Radford,
1990), there is mounting literature to suggest otherwise
(e.g., Braine, 1971; Bowerman, 1973; Tsimpli,
1992; Galasso, 1999). Mixed word order data to this effect suggest
that there may be a very small window in the
chronological development of language that doesn’t reflect
target word order—i.e. a pre-SV(X) stage for
English. In addition, the fact that early child English
seems to provide us with correct word order
recognition may be accounted for by means other than
linguistic motivation—e.g., non- linguistic,
(and perhaps cognitive-based) sequencing strategies
based on formulaic aspects of the input, etc.
(cf. Atkinson, 1992). Recall that the ‘U-shape’ learning
discussed herein shows how possible surface
similarities may actually have very different underpinning
structural realizations—e.g., (i) went
(formulaic) => (ii) go-ed (rule based), =>
(iii) went (rule insertion). While went in (i)
and (iii) look identical
on the surface, they are actually products of two very
different processes. Other various studies on
novel/non-sense verbs similarly reveal a small window
in the duration of staged speech development that
gleams word order errors (Olguin & Tomasello, 1993;
Akhtar & Tomasello, 1997). The child’s inability
to generalize correct word order to novel verbs suggests
that word order, at this early MLU stage,
may be learned on a ‘low-scope’ memorization level one
verb at a time rather than via a
rule- based ‘high-scope’ parameterization process.
Thus, it remains unclear whether or not children’s
very early MLU speech should be credited with having
rule-based processes/parameterizations for
determining word order. If not, a special nativist position
could still be maintained in the sense that
functional parameterization has not yet
taken place (cf. Atkinson op. cit). In light of a potential
stage-1 non-parameterization account for free
word order, strong arguments could be devised suggesting
that instances of free word order, in fact,
demonstrate the early onset of abstract rules—if we
take ‘rules’ here to mean the setting (or
non-setting) of parameters. Such arguments would counter
the general claims being made (cf. Tomasello,
Rowland and Pine (ibid)) that stage-1 is more or less entirely
rote-learned. The fact that we do find word
order errors call for some level of formal rule abstraction—much
in the manner of the U-shape learning model
discussed above.
41. Keeping to the spirit
of Chomsky’s Minimalist Program regarding Word Order, we would
like to maintain Richard
Kayne’s proposal that word order is indeed a universal hierarchical
property of a Spec>Head>Comp relation.
One could perhaps go as far as to make the very strong claim
that SVO mirrors cognition, and thus a universal
order of Subject-Verb-Object is innately given. In any event,
Kayne’s universal constraint is seen as keeping
to the spirit of Chomsky’s innateness hypothesis, and so
we’ll take it as the null hypothesis here and see where
we go with it. However, we can only possibly adhere
to it insofar as the empirical data bear it out—and it is here
that we instantly run into some
difficulties. Mainly speaking, if we want to maintain a
universal SVO order, we therefore must do so at
that stage of development where the child in fact has access
to Double Argument String structures
(DAS). For instance, a prior Single Argument String
stage (=SAS) would have no way of showing the
appropriate Spec and Comp distributions. Well, when looking
at a good cross section of child acquisition data,
it appears that there is no strong evidence pointing to an exclusive
SAS stage—(without some small amount of DASs
interceding). While this may be the case, a stage does evidence
in the data where at least the majority of
utterances are indeed not only SASs, but that such SASs show
variable word orders amongst the Subject/Object
and Verb—rendering SV, VS, OV, VO orders. It is at this juncture
that we have to weaken Kayne’s strong universal
claim for an SVO order as correlated to his Linear
Correspondence Axiom (LCA), and say that such
an axiom only holds for a child at (DAS) stage-2 of
development—again, a stage roughly corresponding with the
(albeit optional) emergence of abstract rule formulations
and functional categories, both which lead to Parameterization.
So in one full sweep, what we have done is
somewhat preserve Chomsky’s original version of a word order
based on Functional Parameterization (pace
Kayne’s strong stance for a non-parameterized word order based
on his universal LCA) and
have added a further Kaynian stipulation by saying that LCA
may only work, rendering
all structures as base generated SVO orders only after a pre-cursor
parameterization has taken place positioning
the Object either Leftward or Rightward of the Verb—now providing
two basic universal orders:
SVO and (the mirror image) OVS: (of course, the latter order
is very rare as a base-generated
order, though some have claimed Japanese as an OVS base order,
and then, via subject movement, derive an
SOV order (fn). In any event, Kayne is explicit in stating that
his Head Medial Principle, (stipulating that
a Head/Verb must remain in middle position and one of the tenets
of his axiom) would conceivably permit the
four word orders above to be accessed by a child in a SAS stage-1