Chesterbelloc
Hist 583, Fall 2006, précis
Diggins, John P. The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest, and the Foundations
of Liberalism.
The greatest of the Roman historians writes, “The more I think about history, ancient or modern, the more ironical all human affairs seem.”[1] One must confess a never failing mood of irony, confirmed by the continued study of history. John Diggins recognizes that the ideological roots of the American republic – classical republicanism and American liberalism – are perceived to be antithetical, i.e., virtue, restraint, and prohibition opposed to the right of self-gratification. Thus politics deals with both the pursuit of virtue and also the containment of viciousness.
Yet Diggins argues that at the nation’s founding, there was very little difference between liberalism and conservatism. Madison and Hamilton, for example, were both liberals:
One expression of liberalism valued
freedom, autonomy and sufficiency of the individual, the other power,
stability, and the efficacy of the state.
Both identified happiness with property and material pleasure; neither
committed
In short, the “self” is never left behind. John Adams certainly did not appeal to man’s
higher nature. He was a moralist whose
pessimism about human nature is mixed with optimism about human potential. His Puritan sensibilities led him to believe
the masses must be protected against themselves; that freedom resides where
there is order and not where there is license, or no order.
For
Diggins, the common ground of American liberalism and conservatism is that both
deny the notion of moral conflict and attendant responsibilities. Granted, the Founders emphasized republican
virtue in 1776 in order to justify the War of Independence. Hence politics is traditionally perceived as a moral endeavor,
addressing questions of right and wrong, dealing with the public dimensions of
the so-called “virtuous life.” But
Diggins declares that the Constitution is a pragmatic document, having nothing
to say about how people ought to live together.
Its sole concern is how to prevent predators from doing one another in; power
is counterpoised against power since, as the saying goes, “mere parchment is no
insurance against oppression.” Like an
arch sustained by the potential force and equality of pressure of separate
stones upon each other, checks and balances are Machiavellian. (A wit might say that both the arch and
check/balance are based on the principle of the Fall.) The Constitution is not morally elevated; it
is Machiavellian also in that politics are divorced from ethics; it is politics
without a soul.[2] It is a social contract dependant upon force to hold it together rather than a covenant of kinship. According to Diggins, the Founders struck a
bargain with Locke, and the price of that deal, rhetoric notwithstanding, was a
break with “the liberal idea of consent that obligated man to respect the
rights of others” (319). For example, the
Founders made a pact of expediency with regard to the moral evil of
slavery. Diggins’s story is therefore of
the classical liberal soul lost at the nation’s founding, found by
The American republic turned the meaning of virtue on its head. Instead of self-restraint and the “greater good,” self-satisfaction became paramount. Classical republican rhetoric achieved little more than negative freedom; to wit, “freedom from political power and public authority, freedom for man to pursue his own ends, individual freedom – in a word, liberalism.” Ironically, Diggins agrees with John C. Calhoun that it is negative power – the power of preventing or arresting the action of the government – that forms the Constitution.[3]
Tocqueville posited that “self-interest rightly understood” bound Americans to one another, making them a people or nation.[4] True, self-interest makes no social distinctions – it applies to the laborer, the outcast, the criminal – but Diggins argues that Tocqueville’s America (which he grudgingly finds acceptable) lasted only until industrialization; that “self-interest rightly understood” degenerated into commercial rapaciousness and impetuous materialism (the new paganism). Hence the English corruption feared by republican revolutionaries in 1776 materialized, undermining the very logic of the Revolution![5] The Catholic Tocqueville hoped for a non-utilitarian religious revival in which virtue would be disassociated from “the rationale of effort and reward so central to modern Protestantism” (251).[6] The idea of virtue however had become firmly identified with self-interest, thereby abnegating the ideals of duty and moral goodness.
Henry Adams
went further, separating virtue from political life altogether. In Adams’s view, capitalism, big business,
and corruption “had so penetrated every layer of society as to render obsolete
the classical distinction between political duty and economic activity, public
good and private interests” (264). The
Founders intended to protect the public against concentrated authority and
predators, but failed to account for “future leviathans” fostered by corporate
wealth. In Oedipal fashion,
Lincoln and
Melville Christianized the American political imagination, returned to the
first principles (and final judgment) of the Declaration, and sought to
reinstate the authority of a Calvinist past, “a past alien to both Jeffersonian
liberalism and classical politics” (298).
The notion of “good” and “evil” returned to American political
discourse, opposed to Machiavellian power and expediency.[13] In his speeches, “
The
greatness of Lincoln lies in the attempt to accomplish the impossible; to
replace classical republican virtues associated with civic humanism with
Christian ideas of righteous judgment (not by humans but by God) and virtues
such as compassion, forgiveness, humility, and sacrifice. A cynic might argue that
There is always a considerable gap between the moral standards of a society and
the practice of the individuals – the higher the standard, the wider the gap.[14] It has been argued that such tension propels
society forward, both morally and materially.
What followed
Comparing
Ronald Reagan with
In sum,
Diggins holds that the liberal idea came at a cost in political
understanding. Plato spoke of the soul
(and perversion of the soul) in political terms. In the modern age, questions of the soul and non-utilitarian
virtue were placed in one corner, and political questions were placed in a
different corner. Influenced by the Enlightenment,
Like
Virginia Woolf’s hero in
[1]
Tacitus, The Annals of Imperial
1956; reprint, 1996), 127
(page citations are to the reprint edition).
[2] See Reinhold Niebuhr, The Irony of American History (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1962), 98. Niebuhr writes: “The Constitution is characterized by awareness of conflicts of power and passion in every community. It knows nothing of a simple harmony in society . . .”
[3] See Russell Kirk, The Conservative Mind: From Burke to Eliot, 7th ed. (Washington, DC: Regnery Publishing, Inc., 1953; reprint, 1995), 175-7.
[4] “Nation”
must be distinguished from “State.”
According to the OED, the former is “a large aggregate of people closely
associated with each other by factors of common descent, language, culture,
history, and occupation of the same territory as to be identified as a distinct
people. . . .” The State, on the other
hand, refers to a political body, i.e., government. It can be argued that self-interest alone
does not make a nation. James McPherson,
in Abraham Lincoln and the Second
American Revolution, writes: “The
[5] See
Drew R. McCoy, The Elusive Republic: Political Economy in Jeffersonian
[6]
Protestant virtues are described by political scientist Eric Voegelin as
“virtues of bourgeois ‘propriety’ adequate for urban and middle class way of
life.” Neither humility, charity, nor
asceticism is written large. “Honesty,
punctuality, cleanliness, dependability, diligence,” writes Voegelin, “can be
called ‘secondary virtues’: virtues
which do not imply any ends in themselves, but must be assigned to determined
goals in order to be positive. . . e.g.,
I can appear punctually at [church] or in the Gestapo cellar” (Eric Voegelin, Hitler and the Germans, in The Collected Works of Eric Voegelin,
ed. Detlev Clemens and Brendan Purcell, vol. 31 (Columbia, Missouri: University of Missouri Press, 1999), 103-04).
[7] The Catechism of the Catholic Church lists four cardinal virtues, none of which involve civics or earthly reward as an end. “The goal of a virtuous life is to become like God” (St. Gregory of Nyssea). According to the Church, the four cardinal human virtues, around which all others are grouped, are: prudence, justice, fortitude, and temperance.
[9]
Richard John Neuhaus, “The Soul of American Politics,” review of John P.
Diggins, The Lost Soul of American
Politics, National Review,
[10] Opposed to the Constitution, the Declaration was based on a secular creed, “enunciating that all men are equal in their claim to justice, that governments exist to give them that justice, and that their authority is for that reason just” (G. K. Chesterton, What I Saw in America [1922], The Collected Works of G. K. Chesterton, vol. 11, ed. George J. Marlin (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1990), 41.
[11] Stated
in metaphysical terms, Grant and Sherman ground Southern valor into powder
because of moral evil, and under a law as mysterious as it is inexorable, all
wrongs must be expiated. Similarly, Counter-Enlightenment
theorist Joseph de Maistre viewed the
Revolutionary Terror as redemption – a cleansing by means of blood – for
toppling the monarchy and thwarting the providential mission of
[12]
Diggins’s description of
[13]
[14] It has been argued that a state of spiritual tension, the constant gap between ideal and practice, has contributed to the spiritual and intellectual dynamism that characterizes Western culture in general. “Where this tension is absent,” writes British historian Christopher Dawson, “where civilization has become ‘autarchic,’ self-sufficient, and self-satisfied, there the process of Christian culture has been extinguished or terminated” (Christopher Dawson, “The Recovery of Spiritual Unity” [1952], Christianity and European Culture: Selections from the Works of Christopher Dawson, ed. Gerald R. Russello (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 1998) 247-8).