One interesting observation here concerning such
(single argument) VS structures has to do with Case assignment.
Most verbs found within VS utterances seem to have Accusative Subjects.
This observation becomes rather significant when coupled with other
data showing correct Nominative Case usage at the same stages of
development (see (9) and (11) below). In other words, the data seem
to demonstrate that when VS order is used, Subjects get Accusative
Case and never Nominative Case. (NB. The notion that such orders
are the result of Dislocations has been largely discredited
by negation initial construction: e.g., Neg-V-S/Neg-O-V (see
§1.3.1)). In fact, not one VS construction yielded a Nominative
Subject. (The fact that Nominative case appears at roughly the same
stage may indicate some sort of optional Nominative/Infl stage).
However, regarding Case assignment to DP, there does seem to be
strong evidence that Genitive Case is unaffected by variable word
order. In fact, the Determiner system emerges fairly early on in
the data and is found in a variety of environments (not to mention
within Language Mixing). The following examples in (9) show correct
Case assignment and Word Order patterns for the same developmental
periods as was shown in examples (7) and (8) above (ex. a, b are
arguably formulaic):
(9)
NOM: SVO |
DP: SVO |
a. I want bottle (file 3: 1;11)
b. I want down (file 6: 2;2)
c. I don't know (file 8: 2;4)
|
d. He cut the tree (file 21: 3;0)
e. I eat my hair (file 19: 2;10)
d. She going touch my man (3;2) |
(Objects)
Examples of OV/VO structures are also found throughout the
range of the data. (Again, recalling our discussion above that word
order errors seem to manifest up until the very last file--dependent
only on the SAS vs. DAS distinction. Token examples are presented
here in (10):
(10)
VO |
OV |
a. Kick the dog (file 4: 2;0)
b. Want my car (file 8: 2;4)
c. No cut train (file 16: 2;8)
d.Cook pasta (file18: 2;9)
(=dad cooks pasta)
e. want bottle (file 10: 2;4)
(=baby wants bottle) (=I don't hit the baby)
f. Make a house (file 24: 3;3)
g. Work at home (file 23: 3;2)
(=He works at home)
|
h. Dog kick (file 3: 1;11)
i. Baby kick (file 11: 2;5)
j. Ball a kick (file 16: 2;8)
k. A egg cook (file 20: 2;11)
l. A cookie eat (file 21: 3;0)
m. No baby hit (file 23: 3;2) |
I think what is crucial to note here is that no overt (INFL)ectional
verbal morphology (excluding the copula Is (e.g., / Iz_ka: />
Is a car) found in file 5) has yet to surface: viz., all of the
VO/OV data suggest that the verb is unspecified for Person. Nominative
Case however, also an indicator of INFL, does seem to be established
in early SV(X) structures, but an asymmetry is found between the
use of Nominative Case in SV and VS structures. The analysis of
OVs and token counts (cf. 10) are given below in (10' & 11):

(WH-Questions) Another
interesting observation is found concerning Wh-Questions. As alluded
to earlier with respect to Kayne, no instances of target word order
violations were found among early Wh-initial (+/-Agr/-Tns) constructions.
Such results might also be used as argumentation in favor of Kayne's
linearization analysis. The arguments might proceed as follows:
(12)
(a). In the event that a (base-generated) Wh-element raises,
occupying a fronted position, the environment for free word order
collapses--recalling earlier that the structure in (5) is restricted
to involving a thematic sisterhood relation prohibiting any A-bar
or Adjunction positions. Thus, either a full-blown VP or CP>VP
structure would project.
(b). Since there would, in principle, be no room for a second
argument (an element other than the Subject and Verb) to position
itself, a raised Wh-element would then be forced to occupy either
an external Spec-CP or possible Adjunction position: both being
A-bar positions--in accordance with the Q-criterion--hence,
violating stipulations placed on (5) (further assuming that any
Adjunction to VP would be driven by some sort of movement operation
creating the chain h....t
). Again, either a full-blown VP or CP>VP would project.
(One possible analysis for the following Wh-constructions is to
suggest that they are Truncated CP>VP structures as proposed
by Radford 1990, 1994, and Roeper and Rohrbacher 1994.)

(* C'=Adjunction p2 as in Kayne's structure in
(4). Simplified by not showing the trace of the Wh-Operator).
An important implication here is that no variable ordering is allowed
within the VP of a CP>VP structure for reasons discussed in (12)--the
Data bear this out. [22] Moreover, a crucial link becomes
available now between the Functional stage (made apparent via O-movement)
and stable word order (within the VP). However noting that INFL
(Agr/Tns) errors still could appear within such structures--as is
evident from (13a'')--since IP is altogether missing from the structure
(as indicated by the absence of Nom case: him doing?).
(Early DP-Projections)
A further observation has to do with the fact that word order
errors seem also to correspond with the absence of the specification
associated with the Head of DP: (possessive 'S).
It is observed in the data that the first attempts to project a
Possessive construction (DP) (within a non-head DAS) fail to realize
the target order. Consider the following examples in (14), where
the Head Possessive 'S is unspecified:
(14)
Spec-(H)-Comp
a. daddy ø truck (file: 3)
b. baby ø car (file: 11)
c. baby ø bottle (file: 12)
|
Comp-(H)-Spec
d. bottle ø baby (file: 12)
e. key ø mama (file: 10)
f. hair ø me (=my (file: 20)) |
The variable word orders cited in (14) could be schematized in
the following ways:
(14')

In (14) above, Genitive Case assignment is assumed to involve a
Spec-Head [+Agr(eement)] relation within DP (Radford: ms1997). The
universal potential orderings of Spec-Comp/Comp-Spec however still
manifest depending on which of the two universal XP schemata is
being utilized.) Again, the crucial claim here relates to the above
observation that variable word orders seem to appear within SAS
or non-Headed DAS projections: it may be that all categories/(phrases)
(Noun (NP), Det (DP), and Verb (VP) alike) are effected in the same
way by the Comp parameter--in this sense, even though we are dealing
with an apparent (Spec/Comp) DAS construct, the crucial point is
that there is no overt Head projection in which to trigger the Comp
parameter (cf. Kayne; ex. (6)). It is interesting to note that once
the Head of DP overtly projects, word order becomes stable (there
are no instances of mixed orders found among specified DP structures).
Consider the counterpart structures in (15):
(15)
a. Baby's hair (file: 25)
b. Car's home (file: 25)
c. Dad's keys (file: 25)
|
d. It's [Zoe's bike] (diary)
e. Where is [Zoe's bottle?] (diary)
f. A boy's bed (diary) |
(15')

The structure in (15') draws attention to a possible
link between the Functional Parameterization Hypothesis (FPH) via
INFL, and the advent of stable word order (at the DAS phase). Namely,
as briefly mentioned above, there seems to be some correlation between
the onset of unstable word order at the SAS phase and the onset
of fixed order at the (FPH) DAS phase. Namely, it is the use of
English Possessive INFL(ection) 'S which signals that the child
has now developed a specifically ENGLISH type of possessive structure
(via INFL) (cf. 15), whereas earlier the child had a 'language-neutral'
type of possessive structure (via Non-INFL) (cf. 14).
What the above data suggest is that it is the acquisition of the
(language-specific) Spec-Head Agreement morphology that
fixes word order. In other words, a Directionality/Linearisation
Principle might say something along the following lines:
Linearisation Principle for Spec-Initial Languages:
A Specifier is positioned to the left of a Head it agrees with.
Non-Agreeing Specifiers (i.e., Adjuncts) may freely insert either
before or after a given Head.
(Bare Infinitives)
Finally, some interesting questions can be raised regarding
a very small set of observed "contradictory" patterns
within Bare Infinitive clauses. These utterances contradict both
proposals I and II in the sense that they involve the overall
Functional IP stage (contradicting the former proposal) and within
(DAS) constructions (contradicting the latter). Consider the distribution
of the following VO/OV word order examples found among (matrix clause)
Nominative-Subjects with Bare Infinitives:
(16)
OVs at IP-stage
a. I going [a plane fly] (=to fly a plane)
b. I want [mama see] (=to see mama)
c. I want [pasta eat] (=to eat pasta) (*
indicates incorrect VO)
|
VOs at IP-stage
d. I want [stop the rain]
e. She going [touch my man]
*f. I want [eat dog] (=dog to eat)
*g. I want [blow me] (=me to blow)
(* indicates incorrect VO)
*h. I want [help me] (=me to help) |
An interesting observation about the distribution of such word
orders is that strict correlations seem to hold between: (i)
Bare Infinitives and variable word orderings, and (ii)
language-specific To-Infinitives and fixed orderings. In
fact, I have no instances of word order errors found within To-Infinitives:
namely, sentences such as e.g., *I want to [mama see (=OV)],
or *I want to [come mama], are not found in the data. Such
apparent overall IP constructions that permit variable word orderings
(within the V-bar) might be accounted for in the following (highly
speculative) manner.
Suppose
that when language specific T(ense) and/or Agr(eement) remain non/under-specified,
the properties relating to how they restrict Directionality become
inert (cf. Tsimpli).
Suppose that such properties regulate directionalities only within
their contained maximal (XP) projections.
Suppose
that the Infinitive particle "to" carries some
sort of (language-specific) anaphoric +Tense (binding) feature--similar
to how to is anaphoric in e.g., He wants to go
where the particle (to) is bound and controlled by the
Verb (wants) in the main clause. This might predict then
that when (non-language-specific) Bare Infinitives appear (i.e.,
without the infinitive particle to), even within Nominative
[+Agr] contexts, their Maximal projection VP contains no anaphoric-bound
+Tense properties from INFL for determining Directionality. In such
a case, this amounts to saying that there exists a split Functional/Lexical
tree--with AGR, T projections involving the top of the tree only
(cf. 17a). Under such a model, we might envisage utterances as (16)
with erroneous OV orders as having the representation below:

What this binding between (a,b)
attempts to illustrate is that the structures of the (lower) VP
seem to share some sort of anaphoric binding relation with
the Tense property of IP: e.g., (iff a
is [+T], then b
is [+T] (situated in Spec-VP)) and the correct directionality of
V/N within V' is set (cf 17b)). It remains unclear exactly what
type of mechanism we are talking about here regarding how the word
order eventually becomes fixed. I can only add at this juncture
that the spirit behind this proposal coincides with the notion discussed
above--namely, that non-language-specific Bare Infinitives represent
an earlier 'single system' (of complementation), and that the eventual
use of the specific English morpheme TO signals the development
of a separate English structure yielding English word order.
3.4 Final Remarks and Residual Problems
(An Additional Grammatical Stage?)
In light of the discussion in the sections above,
a slight refinement might now be proposed for how Developmental
Linguists describe and assess the stages of child language acquisition.
Before the emergence of the VP-stage, commonly referred to as the
Small Clause stage (cf. Radford 1988b), an SAS-phase
may exist permitting a maximum of two words (e.g., Proto-Argument/Predicate)
with an unstable word ordering. The term SAS-phase here doesn't
necessarily mean that three or more words can't project, but rather,
that the majority of utterances found at this phase seem to comprise
of predicate+argument strings only. Furthermore, there is no reason
why such a defined SAS-phase could not, in fact, exist alongside
a DAS-phase--not to mention the possibility that the phase may be
skipped by the child altogether. (In the former case, the child
immediately enters the DAS-stage.) The crucial difference then with
our proposed SAS-phase, as opposed to a VP-stage, would be the added
stipulation that all positions are exclusively A-positions
which are in turn directly Q-marked by the Verb-Head
within V-bar. Such a stipulation renders movement operations invalid
(in adherence to the Theta-criterion--which states that a given
argument can receive only one theta-role). The full range of XP
expressions (viz., the internal argument V' position), though biologically
predetermined to come on-line at the VP-stage, are somewhat suspended
at the SAS-phase until specific properties of lexical items having
to do with principles of X-bar syntax mature.. [23](In this
broader sense, we are talking about the Specifier-Complement asymmetric
opposition at the (DAS) phase which triggers the Complement Directionality
Parameter as mentioned earlier in (§1.2)). The above stated
differences between SASs and DASs amounts to leaving open the question
whether or not movement operations are allowed at the VP-stage.
(Residual Problems under Minimalist Assumptions)
In recapping, one thing the two proposed models seem
to have in common (cf. (i) Tsimpli, and (ii) a
'weakened' Kayne) is the fact that they both rely on traditional
notions of X-bar syntax: notions that have generally been dispensed
with within Bare Phrase Structure (Chomsky 1995: Ch.4). The following
cited residual problems take into account more recent interpretations
of Bare Phrase Structure regarding Word Order.
(Merger)
Before moving on to the residual problems,
let's first briefly examine how the operation Merge itself
might be broken down and analyzed into more fundamental components.
Recall that the structure in (5) amounted to a Proto-Argument+Predicate
construction. In order to derive the reduced tree in (5), aspects
of Merge must also be capable of yielding a reduced tree. It is
in this light that we conclude Merge to be formed by two rather
independent operations: [24]
(18)
(i) Primary Merger--Merge Head with Comp (zero
level category takes complement)

(ii) Secondary Merger--Merge Spec with Non-Maximal
Projection (X or X')--
[Spec + X/X'] => XP

The notion behind (5) is presented above in the form
of the secondary merger operation--viz., merge Head with Spec. However,
the redefinition of Spec in (5) as a Proto-Argument, and not a true
Specifier, is crucial to maintaining the reduced tree in (5). In
other words, the child begins her linguistic career (SAS phase)
by engaging the second merger operation first--as it is the only
operation available--whereby the "Spec" becomes reorganized
as the Proto-Argument slot into which Subjects and Objects alike
may enter:

The above observations regarding Merge can be summarized
in the following manner:
(1) The child begins projecting simple phrasal SASs by first merging
the non-maximal projection of a Head with the external argument
Specifier (noting that this Specifier encompasses both Subject and
Objects). (NB. The need for the child to identify early-on the external
argument hierarchy might be closely linked to inherent and innate
principles of X-bar syntax. [25]That
is, XP [=external Spec+Head] may be hard-wired-in from the beginning
and not prone to any maturational factors or parameterizations,
etc.)
(2) Once the child begins to project Double Argument Strings (DAS),
as witnessed by her usage of both Spec and Comp positions, the XP
schema is seen as being fully-fledged--thus deriving the potential
VP-Shell (cf. Larson) where both Specifiers and Complements are
highly active (for reasons having to do with movement operations,
etc.) VP-shells, in this sense, are naturally derived from DAS constructions.
Target Word Order is set via a coupling of (i) Kayne's
Head-Medial Principle and (ii) the eventually setting
of the Comp Parameter that triggers correct word order via
an agreeing Specifier relation with the Head. Once the VP-shell
projects, the functional non-thematic stage has commenced, allowing
movement operations and A-bar positions to flourish.
(VP-Shell)
The Larsonian VP-shell, I believe, contains two
essential ingredients for supporting the proposal at hand. They
are as follows:
First, the original definition of Subjects and Objects as symmetric
and mnemonic place holders (i.e., Agr-S/O respectively) stems directly
from Pollock's (1989) theory which takes the Agreement relation--be
it Subject or Objects--to be of a Spec-Head nature. This subsequently
allows the Specifier position to be non-prejudicial in permitting
an Object to project from out of a Spec position. This holds important
consequences for how we, in turn, account for the structure in (5)
restated above in terms of Merger Theory. Specifically, since the
Spec position may now be seen, theoretically, to host the Object,
we can now dispense (for the time being) with the Comp position
since it needn't project at all for the early SAS phase. Moreover,
the traditional idea claiming Head-Comp to be the "most local-relation"
(i.e., thematic) needn't be jeopardized, since all arguments at
the SAS phase are thematic, regardless of their relationships: e.g.,
the external Spec being Q-marked
by its sister X'.
Second, the Larsonian VP-Shell further supports this notion by addressing
the problems associated with the Theta-markings of multiple internal
arguments, etc. Consider the underlying structure of a 3-place predicate
sentence (e.g., John put the book on the shelf) where the
Object the book is placed in Spec VP:
(20)
(Proposal I))
One notable problem for Tsimpli's model has to do with the assumption
of a fully-fledged VP structure at the two-word stage. For instance,
consider the child's typical Single Argument String utterance in
(I) where only a Specifier and Verb projects:

Regarding current notions of Merger, the
idea that a 'traditional' V-bar configuration should inherently
take the initial role of merging two syntactic objects [a2,
b] forming a new
combined syntactic object [a1] is, I think, an intuitive assumption (cf. Chomsky
1995:226, 245). (I fully recognize that some traditional arguments
for XP are no longer maintained within Bare Phrase Structure; however,
Chomsky does continue to recognize the Head-Complement relation
as the most "fundamental" and "local" relation.)
However, in (I) above, it is the Specifier and Head which would
seem to Merge leaving this fundamental sister Complement position
of the Head empty. (This would be counterintuitive, suggesting that
children (at the SAS phase), in fact, do recognize that the full
XP hierarchy projects). Under Kayne's revised model presented in
proposal II, the (SAS) utterance "Baby cry" would
be derived by the Merging of
[a b] forming [a']
(order irrelevant) via the only relation possible (local or otherwise)
between a Proto-Argument (Spec) and Predicate (Head):
(II)

|
In-note
I acknowledge that Kayne's model is
inconsistent with Chomsky 1995--
where merger theory excludes non-
branching single-bar categories.
In light of Chomsky's discussion of
Baby cry Kayne (p.338), such a reduced two
segment structure might be looked
on as having an internal Adjunct
structure ( i)
|
The reduced structure in (II), I believe, captures both the essence
of what is innately given for the child--i.e., her innate ability
to realize that X-bar syntax must contain an external branch for
the proto-argument--while, at the same time, offering us an account
of how the child strings such SASs together.
Secondly, a pre-minimalist claim that movement operations might
be inoperative at the VP stage, being restricted to Functional categories,
has recently been challenged by the notion that lexical Verbs may
raise into the light-verb position within double VP-shell
structures (Larsonian Shell)--assigning respective q-roles to object, indirect object along the way. Such movement
operations would undoubtedly require a trace: in this respect. In
light of this, it now becomes rather questionable why the VP-stage
should be incapable of (i) movement operations (per se)
and/or (ii) the setting of correct word order.
Recall Tsimpli's account that argued what initially impeded the
setting of word order at the VP-stage was the total lack of non-thematic/Functional
categories. Well, Atkinson notes (1992:295 fn1) that the relative
ordering of the Head Verb and its Complement ought not be parameterized
by the FPH whatever the case--since Theta-role assignment is a property
of lexical heads and Objective Case is typically assigned by Verbs,
a lexical category. Atkinson's argument hints that a fixed (VP-stage)
word order does not seem too unreasonable--since word order may
not be dependent on functional categories, but rather on a relational
property of Spec>Head>Comp. The obvious problem however with
this is that (based on acquisition literature) we indeed find DAS
word order errors at the proper VP-stage (albeit rarely).
It is not clear what the reasons would be under Kayne's original
account. I suppose however, that under Kayne's 'weakened' version
(modified here), which takes a two-pronged Directionality model--coupling
the Head-Medial Principle with that of the Complement
Parameter--a feasible reason having to do with the nature of
parameterization itself might be given. Namely, once the two arguments
project, a certain amount of time is still required to correctly
set the [Complement Directionality] parameter. Hence, a variety
of SVO, OVS might briefly appear before the actual setting of correct
word order (see note 6). Moreover, recapping the notion put forward
regarding the Larsonian Shell, a rather different story could likewise
be run suggesting that all word order variations--other than SVO,
OVS--found at the DAS VP-stage are indeed actually derivations involving
movement.
(Proposal II)
The most outstanding problem for Kayne's approach to word order
lies in his dependence on category-terminal distinctions. In Chomsky's
Bare Phrase Structure, there is no such distinction. Thus a typical
counterpart of (3) above would be the following:
(III)

The problem in (III) above is that (m, p) break asymmetrical
c-command (ACC) since there is no hierarchical maximal projecting
terminal node in the Complement position (p). Chomsky however finds
a way to save (ACC) by making a somewhat strong stipulation that
either all Complement categories must be a Complex category (with
both terminal/non-terminal nodes), or that all right branching structures
must end in a trace. (I will not go into the complicated details
here, suffice it to say here that such strong stipulations would
undoubtedly have ramifications for language acquisition)
A second and perhaps more fundamental problem regards the final
result--as predicted by Epstein (ibid)--that (LCA) would likewise
make available OVS as a (UG) base-generated pattern. There is little
evidence to suggest that this pattern actually occurs at all cross-linguistically.
Joseph Greenberg (1963) notes regarding Universals that OVS occupies
roughly (2%) of the world's languages--a major empirical hurdle
to get around (see note 11). At best, it would have to be claimed
that OVS is a base structure that simply doesn't survive without
immediate morphologically driven movement (at PF)--for one reason
or another. (Japanese as a potential OVS language might fall into
this category: cf., Tonoike 1995).
In sum, this chapter on Word Order overall has demonstrated that
indeed a Phase does exist in the acquisition of language where variable
word orders are permitted: including both SV/VS, VO/OV structures.
The availability of such free orderings was seen to be predominately
linked to the early two-word VP-stage (described as the SAS phase,
although variant ordered SASs partially continued into the otherwise
IP-stage). Utilizing a 'weakened' model of Kayne's LCA (which, in
its original form, called for a Spec-Head-Comp universal hierarchy),
we showed how the Comp Parameter could establish the correct word
order. This finding supported Bowerman's claim that it is the emergence
of both overt arguments (viz., the Subject's vs. Object's competitive
drive to secure a Spec-position) within a syntactic DAS structure
that contributes to the correct setting of the Word Order Parameter.
The findings in the data were also made consistent with Tsimpli's
work that likewise gave evidence of free word order at the early
VP stage. However, we differed with Tsimpli in a number of respects--namely,
that free word order was not seen to involve Double Arguments Strings
(DAS), and that the correct setting of word order was not seen as
a sole consequence of Functional Parameterization, but rather as
a result of the two-pronged condition placed on (i) the
Head Medial Principle, as well as (ii) the Comp Parameter--in
this sense, it was the placement of the Complement in opposition
to the Specifier (creating an agreeing Spec) which brought about
either universal word order setting: SVO or OVS. The notion that
clauses start-off with a minimal VP-structure (a reduced XP), and
thenceforth expand as required (once newly acquired structures project),
is consistent with the overall Structure-Building model assumed
here.
<<
Back to Index
Chapter
3 Notes
[21] C in adult grammars are assumed to be strong--thus motivating
movement in its requirement to be filled. In the child grammar,
however, C might remain weak. See also chapter 5 for a more detailed
discussion of CP.
[22] The data however could also be consistent with the view
that when you have Wh-movement, full functional CP>IP>VP
structures are in place.
[23] See Atkinson (1992: 213) for an in-depth discussion
of a maturational based language acquisition programme. (See also
Borer et Wexler 1987). For recent accounts of the development
of Broca's area regarding the maturation of neural connectivity,
(see Simonds et Scheibel 1989, Greenfield 1991, Bickerton
1995, and Wakefield et Wilcox 1995). Bickerton (1992) suggests
that the X-bar scheme itself reflects certain neural connectors
in the brain which are prone to maturation.
[24] The notion of a dual merger operation here is taken
from Andrew Radford (pc).
[25] . Of course, it is feasible to consider, at this SAS
phase, that the child starts-off with a flat structure--in which
we have X and XP but not X-bar. This would have the flavor of
saying that the child starts by projecting one flat structure
until such a time when she comes across more data (DASs) which
forces her to project a hierarchical structure. E.g., the need
to integrate a third constituent somewhere into her scheme would
then force her to provide a full XP. My proposal regarding a 'weakened
Kayne' account could work within such a framework. This would
match Radford's Uniform Bar Expansion Hypothesis.
[26] An interesting note here regards the possibility that
only a VP-shell (via movement) can break symmetric configurations/word
orders that arise within certain small clauses ( where neither
constituent dominates the other). Where e.g., [is [sc[the
cause of the riot] [the picture on the wall]]] = (i) The cause
of the riot t was the picture on the wall; or (ii) The
picture on the wall was the cause of the riot t. Only via
movement in the VP-shell is the symmetry broken and XP dominance
restored (cf. Moro 1997).
*
Text taken out of J.A. Galasso (1999) ‘The Acquisition of Functional
Categories: A Case Study. (Ph.D. Diss. Essex University (Ch 3)).
For references, see Galasso (1999/2003) (Essex/IULC Press).
|