4. Final Remarks and Conclusion
(Word Order)
One interesting aspect of Word Order is that it
becomes fixed once DASs project. However, in light of this, it seems
that SASs and DASs do occur alongside one another (with only the
SAS counterpart allowing variable orderings). Thus, it becomes rather
difficult to refer to the two modes here as individual stages. In
this sense, the eventual correct setting of word order, as partially
brought about by the Comp Parameter, is also dependent
upon the non-parameterized workings of LCA coupled with DAS (Kayne
op.cit.). This is made apparent by the fact that if word order were
based purely on Parameterization (for example, via some
functional category), then word order should be correctly set for
the entire range of XP-structures found a the presumed parameterized
stage--given the emergence of DASs (be it for SASs or DASs alike).
As we see from the data here, accounts of word order based purely
on parameterization don't suffice--this seems to support Kayne's
claim for a "Non-Parameterized" LCA.
One additional piece of support in favor of a dual SVO vs. OVS base-generated
pattern comes from Sam Epstein (Chomsky 1995: 391 fn108) who notes
that Kayne's LCA allows free temporal ordering (either left-to-right,
et vice versa). E.g., a satisfied LCA could have any arrangement
of (sister) Head-Comp, Comp-Head relations (read-books, books-read
freely). It is in this sense that I couple LCA with a Comp-Parameter.
(Underspecification)
There has been some talk that the two prevailing
schools-of- thought (as cited within) may eventually be forced together--on
principled grounds--by Chomsky's Merger Theory. What I
am on about here is the idea that certain features may Merge while
others get postponed--irrespective of the category which binds them.
In other words, a new brand of classification may be in the making--i.e.,
categorizing +Interpretable vs. -Interpretable
features constructs. For reasons of time and space, I won't go on
about in here. But, in what I believe is a sample of things to come,
reflect on the idea of traditional Functional Categories (DP, CP)
as being able to project at the earliest MLU stage (say, at our
stage-1 here) via +Interp(retable) features only (i.e., merge can
operate on partial feature sets.) What would one claim about this
stage? Since category labels no longer enter into the equation-and
we now forfeit the very criteria that once spun old debates on Structural
Continuity--the notion of a VP-stage becomes irrelevant. In other
words, the issue here is that functional categories (DP, IP, CP)
encode both [+Interp] and [-Interp] features (Agr = [-Interp] for
IP). In the event that all [-Interp] formal features are lacking
at stage-1, would a proto functional category actually be functional
or lexical? (See also §5 below).
(Wh-Movement)
(For further arguments against an overall Adjunction
account, see Galasso: 1999). Suffice it to say here that any adjunction
account for such early, seemingly thematic structures would entail
some sort of movement analysis. With such analyses, it becomes exceedingly
difficult to account for the wide-spread failure of movement operations
and functionalism which usually accompany movement: viz., the cited
deficits in Inflectional markings of Tense, Agreement (IP), and
Aux Inversion (CP) etc. (See section 2 above for a Non-Inflectional
Stage-1). In sum, although children may use Wh+Copula+N
constructs as early as MLUw 2.3, such constructs are relegated to
being either (i) semi-formulaic in nature or (ii)
base-generated strings not involving movement operations where a
simple VP projects in order to accommodate the copula verb. An interesting
side-note here is that Roeper et al. similarly claim (albeit in
reverse effect) that once children come to move Wh-expressions into
Spec-CP, they cease to produce subjectless Wh-questions (cited from
Radford 1996: 61). What I am suggesting is in fact an opposite 'cause
& effect' relation--namely, it is due to the subject surfacing
which eventually forces the Wh-element to position into Spec-CP
(adhering to Cinque).
(Formulaic Wh)
The three types of early Wh-constructs which all
come out as semi-formulaic are the following: (i) What that,
(ii) What's/is that, (iii) Where's +N--and are all taken from
files 1-8). Somewhat similar Wh+Copula+N constructs which appear
starting from file 9 (onward) conversely get considered as maintaining
a CP structure via structural continuity (IP truncations notwithstanding).
(See Hickey 1993 for criteria).
(A Recap)
The data (above) suggest there to be an initial
No-Inflection Stage-1 during which Subject-Verb
and Possessor Agr are not marked--a stage characterized by the use
of default Objective Possessors/Subjects and the omission of Poss.
'S and third person S. Compare and contrast Stage-1 vs. Stage-2
respectively: (Me car vs. My car; Daddy car vs. Daddy's car;
You car vs. Your car; Him car vs. His car; Me/Him go vs. I/He go(es);
"What's that" vs. What ø daddy doing/What is daddy
doing?) This Optional Stage-2 last until the end of
the recordings (file: 25, 3;6), though by file 25, INFL is generally
established. The incremental emergence of possessors like His (emerging
late in file 24, Table 2.3) demonstrates that different lexical
items are acquired at different rates and ages, and likewise, their
independent incremental onsets of INFL-related development seem
to suggest that the feature specifications involved are lexical-specific
(pace Schütze et Wexler), and not dependent upon 'higher-order'
phrase structures: IP can be well established for some lexical items
e.g., Poss. My = [+Agr] while being totally nonexistent for other
items, e.g., Him = [-Agr] for that same period.
(Conclusion)
In conclusion, what we have suggested here is
a (manageable) merging of two extreme positions. Firstly, by acknowledging
the strongest case scenario as the Null Hypothesis, (Minimise Degrees
of Freedom Principle (cf., Hyams 1994)), we appease Continuity Theory.
Secondly, and to the delight of the Structure-Builders among us,
we slightly 'weaken' the null hypothesis by one degree only: stipulating
that in order for any full competence theory to be set in practice,
VP-Eligibility must first be exhausted. In other words,
if a (prosaic) VP can theoretically handle the relevant material
found among the very early stage of language development, then,
by virtue of principles of economy of projection (Roeper et al.
1994), it must. However, principles of economy only work in conjunction
with this deduced principle of VP-Eligibility--as a natural consequence
of Economy--viz., once projected material can no longer be secured
within a Q-VP, it must manifest within its destined full-continuity
structure. Justification for this approach is self-evident. Following
M. Atkinson (op.cit: 32), we can suppose that: [i]f two periods
of the data are sufficiently far apart, these sets of data will
exhibit rather clear qualitative differences allowing us to
construct grammars G1
(=VP stage) and G2 (=IP/CP-Optional
stage) (respectively) (emphases belong to MA). In this sense, we
have shown in general that functional categories do seem to follow
at prior stage where (primitive) VPs, along with other lexical categories,
function in isolation (i.e., the lexical VP-stage). This was the
case with INFL (cf. 2), where a Non-Inflectional Stage-1 preceded
a Wexlerian OI-Stage. Likewise, a Wh-VP stage (cf. 3), theoretically,
was posited to be in advance of a potential CP-stage. I believe
in maintaining these above stances, we come full circle in highlighting
traditional differences between the Full Competence vs. Structure-Building
schools. This view could be summed-up as follows: from the beginning,
there was never much real distance between the two schools (both
schools acknowledge that Principles of UG must constrain all possible
grammars.)10 Recent
notions of Underspecification have certainly exemplified this--seemingly
putting the Structure-Builders on the defensive. However, in full
view of the data presented here, the successful 'weakening' of such
strong stances has shown once again the (proper) gap between
the two schools. By taking the strongest hypothesis (concerning
Continuity) as the Null Hypothesis, and then by essentially working
backwards and weakening it on a 'need-to-need' basis in order to
accommodate the empirical data, we have essentially returned (once
again) to the ghosts of bygone orthodoxies: so let's ask the same
old familiar question once more (overleaf)--
<<< Do children start-off their grammatical lives
with a complete system of syntactic representation...or
not? And if so, how can we tell >>>
(emphases belong to Atkinson 1995: 29).
5. Residual Problems, Alternative Solutions and Future
Research
The following is a highly condensed version of a discussion on Merger
Theory found in Galasso (1999). It is presented here merely as a
caveat to the aforementioned outstanding issue regarding child formulaic
constructs.
In spite of an embarrassing wealth of literature about well know
facts on formulaicy in early child speech, (see Brown 1968,
Hickey 1993), the notion behind formulaic analyses seems nonetheless
to grate on the minds of some researchers today whom esteem to grant
the benefit of doubt to the child in any event (and at whatever
cost). I myself, among many, personally believe such a granting
to be overly optimistic and ill-managed, typically in light of the
sort of data the child produces/comprehends at the given stage.
However, in acknowledging that there is a potential issue here,
and in the event that formulaic accounts do become increasingly
unattainable (e.g., there is ongoing research to suggest that children
might comprehend Wh-Questions even before they can talk, cf. Radford:
pc), I propose below a broad alternative account to default/formulaic
grammars which could continue to uphold Structure-Building models
of acquisition.
I. (Reconsidering DP)
The traditional idea of functional categories
have recently been complicated by the introduction of notions of
feature specifications and projections (as cited in Chomsky: 1995,
§4 Merger Theory). In Chapter 4 of my Ph.D. Diss., I tease
out issues in how we can come to grip with a seemingly functional
DP projection in an otherwise (manifesting) Lexical VP stage. In
a nutshell, what I discover is that all such DPs used at this hypothetical
VP-stage-1 go consistently under/non-specified for formal features
[-Interp(retable)] such as Case. By extended hypothesis, I went
on to claim (following Radford pc) that such DPs could specify for
[+Interp] features only--namely, [+Def(initess)] which would not
require any formal checking. This is tantamount to saying that e.g.,
The within such DPs take-on Case via default and show no
other signs of functionalism. I labelled the DPs as either (i)
DP>VP or (ii) DP>IP--seeking to express the contrast
between DPs which pertain more to the lexical-substantive category
VP, contra the traditional classification of a formal functional
DP:
(i) a. John's car goes =[D/P0 [IP
John ['s [car]]] ]*..goes [+Agr] (DP>IP)
b. John car go = [D/P0 John car]...go
[-Agr] (DP>VP)
(*Bracket
structures are simplified to show only the relevant agreement.)
This
attempt to redefine traditional notions of categories and phrases
in terms of the features that project--viz., [+Interp vs. -Interp]--drastically
changes the landscape in how we can assess functional vs. lexical
categorial distinction.
II. (Reconsidering CP)
Following in the wake of such
underspecified DPs (above), it is not too inconceivable to then
propose a similar analysis to underspecified CPs (likewise found
at the otherwise patterned VP stage). The parallel [+Interp] feature
for CP (as it has to do with Wh-elements) would be Chomsky's notion
of a Q-feature (=Interrogativeness). E.g., Chomsky (1995: 289) suggests--that
Q is plainly [+Interp]; therefore, like the phi-features of
a nominal, it need not be checked (unless strong). Such a treatment
of Wh-elements puts them on a par as a variant of D (e.g., What
book=DP). Thus, the distinctions drawn-on above concerning
D(P)s now have relevance here to C(P)s as well.
Suppose, for Child English, we take Q to be initially set (or unparameterized)
to a default 'weak setting' (until further sufficient input on Wh-raising
sets it otherwise). Then, Q doesn't raise for checking.
Suppose, for Child English, Q only initially projects this [+Interp]
feature. The parallels of the two arguments become ever so apparent--i.e.,
there is nothing in principle which would prevent us from saying
that, like DPs (before them), CPs may also receive a form of default
setting.
(ii) a. What car go = [C/P0 (VP)...[DP
What car]]*...go... [-Agr] (CP>VP)
b. What car goes = [C/P0 (IP)...[DP What
car]]....goes [+Agr] (CP>IP)
c. Whose car = [C/P0 (DP)...[IP Who
's car]] [+Agr] (CP>IP)
(*Bracket Structures are
simplified to show only the relevant agreement) This
amounts to saying that in spite of a seemingly (straightforward
and traditional) CP analysis, such Wh-sentences may be reduced to
projecting in one of three base-generated manners via a VP. More
specifically, the DP in e.g., What car go may select the
following available landing sites: (i) a Spec-VP, (ii)
an Adjunct VP, or finally (iii) a Spec CP>VP (with a
[+Interp] feature only)--the essential point being here that all
three constructs would possibly show no movement. In the latter
sense (iii) (exemplifying +Interpretable features here),
Roeper & Rohrbacker's CP>VP truncated account could be reinterpreted
as ultimately being base-generated.
In full spirit of the proposal sketched above, we then are left
with only Agr/T (=IP) to consider. Following Chomsky's (1995, Ch.4)
remark that only Agr is left to constitute pure non-Interp features--and
having shown how the remaining functional categories DP & CP
might be reducible to their substantive feature-projections--we
take IP to be the functional category par excellence. As
a consequence of no INFL-related material, the feasibility of a
CP>DP/VP structure projecting from the earliest MLUw stage may
not entirely jeopardize an otherwise seemingly straightforward Structure-Building
account of language acquisition. (See Galasso 1999, Chapter 4 for
DP & Chapter 5 for CP.)
III. (Future Research: Issues
in Specific Language Impairment)
The protracted nature of language acquisition as drawn up here
certainly may aid developmenal linguists and language pathologists
interested in accounting for specific areas of delayed grammatical
development in some cases regarding Specific Language Impaired individuals
(SLI). Whether it be stroke victims suffering from Left/Right Hemispheric
damage, or children with Focal Lesions, to instances of Aphasia,
I believe a better understanding of the natural language process
at hand among normal children can serve as a road-map to uncovering
exactly where the linguistic anomalies will surface in the speech
output--leading perhaps to better methodologies in therapy. To put
this on more concrete grounds, take for example recent reports dealing
with in vivo PET studies. Although such early studies--which
initially set out to locate and map precise areas of language activity
in the brain--have come about with not much success (see Peterson,
Fox, Posner, Mintun, and Raichle 1989), there nonetheless have been
some sound reports cited to suggest that when a part of language
is indeed effected, the effected part pertains to the more formal
aspect of language--particularly those categories dealing with Inflectional
Morphology and/or Case. This seems to go hand-in-hand
with the standard assumption that suggests that Neural Plasticity--which
speaks to a critical period of language acquisition: (cf. Lenneberg
1967)--may facilitate recovery more in children than in more mature
subjects. In short, this has the flavor of saying that it is those
more formal categories of language--i.e., categories prone to maturational
development such as Inflection, Agreement paradigms, and Case (cited
herein)--which seem to be effected most due to their having a qualitatively
different mapping system in the neural make-up of the brain.
Although research concentrating on the effects of Left/Right hemispheric
damage is still in its infancy, some early signs suggest that significant
delays show up in the child's usage of morphological inflections--including
plural, possessive, present progressive, and regular past tense
(-ed) forms (Fenson et al. 1993). (See Galasso 1999 paper no.
2 in prep. for further discussion). If by examining the type of
errors made by normal children we begin to spot similarities to
that of SLI children, we may begin to hypothesis exactly where and
how language problems will arise.
In closing, the overall analysis presented here may shed some
light on what we know about SLI individuals. The fact that Word
Order, INFLectional, as well as Movement Operations
seem to be the last of a series of systems to mature due to their
abstract nature, it therefore should be of no surprise to find that
certain similarities hold with respect to 'what gets missed
out where' when contrasting the SLI speech of young-adults.
It may very well be the case that some SLI individuals simply have
a higher threshold with regards to what amount of formal speech
input is required in order to trigger a certain formal system into
production. This amounts to saying that a five-to-six year old typical
SLI child may be in parallel development to that of a two-to-three
year old normal child. Perhaps, it could only be such an analysis
that ultimately accounts for scattered reports which tend to show
that the speech of young SLI children eventually does catch-up to
the appropriate normal level of linguistic production.
The main aim of the second paper is to focus primarily on the
Quantitative/Qualitative measurements behind an SLI individual--using
what has been found and discussed in this paper as a theoretical
starting point from which to precede.
Acknowledgments
This paper represents a rather simplistic view of my Ph.D. Diss.
(1999). I am grateful first and foremost to Andrew Radford (Essex)
(my mentor and Ph.D. supervisor) for his valuable comments on earlier
drafts of this paper. I also thank Sam Featherston for his reading
through an earlier draft, and Harald Clahsen (Essex) for lending
me access to his data-base coding convention. I thank Hiro Matsumoto
for our lengthy discussions on Kayne.
<<
Back to Index
References
Atkinson,
M. (ms.1995) Now, hang on a minute: some reflections on
emerging orthodoxies. Essex Research Reports In Linguistics:
Vol.7 pp. 29ff. University of Essex.
Bickerton,
D. (1990) Language & Species. The University of Chicago
Press: Chicago
Bowerman,
M. (1973) Early Syntactic Development. Cambridge University
Press: Cambridge.
(1990) 'Mapping Thematic Roles onto Syntactic Functions: are
children helped by innate linking rules?' Linguistics 28.
pp.1253-1289 Walter de Gruyter.
Brown,
R. (1973) A First Language: The Early Stages. George
Allen and Unwin: London
Chomsky,
N. (1981) Lectures on Government and Binding. Foris, Dordrecht
Press.
(1995) The Minimalist Program. MIT Press: Cambridge,
Mass.
Cinque,
G. (1990) Types of A'-Dependencies. MIT Press: Cambridge,
Mass.
Clahsen,
H. (1986) 'Verb Inflections in German Child Language: acquisition
of agreement markings and the functions they encode'. Linguistics,
24: 79-121.
Clahsen,
H.; Eisenbeiss, S.; Penke, M.(1995) "Lexical Learning in Early
Syntactic Development". In H. Clahsen (Ed.) Generative Perspectives
on Language Acquistion. Benjamins: Amsterdam
Felix,
S.(1984) 'Maturational Aspects of Universal Grammar'. In A. Davis,
C. Criper and A. Howatt (eds). Interlanguage. Edinburgh Univ.
Press: Edinburgh.Fenson,
L. (1993), Dale, P.S., Reznick, J.S., Thal, D., Bates, E., Hartung,
J. Pethick, S. and Railly, J. The MacArthur Communicative development
Inventories. San Diego.
Galasso,
J. (1994-1998) The N-Corpus. (Personal Data-Base compiled
from 8,000+ analyzable sentences. Coding convention was established
by H. Clahsen (1984) University of Essex).
Galasso,
J. (1999a) The Acquisition of Functional Categories: A Case Study.
Unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation. University of Essex.
(1999b) A Working Paper on Second Language Acquisition Research:
Some Notes on Theory and Method. Unpublished Manuscript. San
Diego State University Summer, 1999 (Class Lectures taken from Linguistics
550).
(In prep) Grammatical Development and Language Disorders
(Paper no. 2). Unpublished manuscript. Long Beach City College.
Hickey,
T.(1993) 'Identifying Formulas in First Language Acquisition'.
J. of Child Language 20: 57-125.
Hoekstra,
T., Hyams, N., Becker, M. (1996a) The role of the specifier and
finiteness in early grammar. Paper presented to the child language
seminar: Reading, April 1996.
(1996b) The underspecification of number and the licensing
of root infinitives. Paper presented to the Boston University
Conference on Language Development.
Hyams,
N. (1995) 'The Underspecification of Functional Categories in Early
Grammar'. In Harald Clahsen (ed) Generative Perspectives on Language
Acquisition. Benjamins: Amsterdam pp. 91-127
Kayne,
R. (1994) The Antisymmetry of Syntax. MIT Press: Cambridge,
Mass.
Klima,
E.S., and Bellugi, U. (1966) 'Syntactic Regularities in the Speech
of Children'. Psycholinguistic Papers. (eds) J. Lyons &
R. Wales. Edinburgh Univ. Press.
Lenneberg,
E. ( 1967) Biological Foundations of Language. Wiley Press:
New York.
Peters,
A. (1983) The Units of Language Acquisition. Cambridge Univ.
Press: N.Y.
(1995) 'Strategies in the Acquisition of Syntax.' In P. Fletcher
& B. MacWhinney (eds). The Handbook of Child Language
pp.462 ff. Blackwell: Cambridge, Mass.
Peterson,
S.E., (1989) Fox, P.T., Posner, M.I., Mintun, M., and Raichle, M.E.
'Positron emission: tomographic studies of the cortical anatomy
of single-word processing'. Nature 331, 585-9
Pierce,
A. (1989) On the emergence of syntax: a crosslinguistic study.
Diss., MIT.
Radford,
A. (1990) Syntactic Theory and the Acquisition of English Syntax.
Basil Blackwell: Cambridge, Mass.
(1994a) Syntactic Theory and the Structure of English.
Cambridge Univ. Press.
(1994b) 'The Syntax of Questions in Child English'. Journal
of Child Language: 21. pp.211-236. Cambridge University
Press.
(1995) 'Phrase Structure and Functional Categories'. In Paul
Fletcher and Brain MacWhinney (eds). The Handbook of Child Language.
pp.483-507. Blackwell: Cambridge, Mass.
(1996) 'Towards a Structure-Building Model of Acquisition'.
In H. Clahsen (ed) Generative Perspectives on Language Acquisition.
Benjamins: Amsterdam.
Radford,
A. and Galasso, J. (1998ms) Children's Possessive Structures:
A Case Study. University of Essex.
Rizzi,
L. (1986) 'Null Subjects in Italian and the theory of pro.' Linguistic
Inquiry 17 pp.501ff
Roeper,
T. 'The Role of Merger Theory and Formal Features in Acquisition'.
In Clahsen (ed) Generative Perspectives on Langauge Acquisition.
Benjamins: Amsterdam.
Roeper,
T., and Rohrbacher, B. (1994) Null subjects in early child English
and the theory of economy of projection. (ms. to appear in Linguistic
Inquiry).
Schütze,
C. (1997) INFL in Child and Adult Language: Agreement, Case and
Licensing. Diss., MIT.
Tsimpli,
I.M. (1992) Functional Categories and Maturation: The Prefunctional
Stage of Language Acquistion. Diss., University College London.
Wexler,
K. (1994) 'Optional Infinitives, head movement and the economy of
derivation'. In D. Lightfoot and N. Hornstein (eds) Verb Movement.
Cambridge Univ. Press p305f
Schütze,
C. & Wexler, K. (1996) 'Subject Case Licensing and English Root
Infinitives'. In A. Stringfellow, D. Cahana-Amitay, E. Hughes
and A. Zukowski (eds) Proceedings of the 20th Boston University
Conference on Language Development: Vol.2. Cascadilla Press:
Somerville, Mass. pp.670-681.
Tonoike,
S. (1995) 'Japanese as an OVS Language'. In S. Haraguchi & M.
Funaki (Eds) pp. 105-133
Wakefield,
J. & Wilcox, M.J. (1995) 'Brain Maturation and Language Acquisition:
A theoretical model and preliminary investigation'. Proceedings
of the 19th Annual Boston University Conference on
Language Development. 2 vols,(eds) by D. MacLaughlin & S.
McEwen. pp.643-654. Cascadilla Press: Somerville, Mass.
Winjen,
F. and Bol, G. (1993) "The Escape from the Optional Infinite
Stage'. Papers in Experimental Linguistics: Univ. of Groningen:
pp. 239ff.
Section
1 (on Kayne) was presented at the Annual Research Presentation at
the University of Essex (20, May 1998).
END NOTES
10 Here, I
speak against notions of 'wild grammars' (Felix 1984). Moreover,
tactics for defining absolute feature-nonspecificity (for the proposed
stage-1) could equally be cast within Structure-Building models--with
more traditional questions like 'How do category/phrase types emerge
and develop?' being replaced by the now relevant question--'How
do particular feature types develop?' |