(Additional Errors) Notwithstanding the abundant usage
of correct Genitive Case regarding the Optional Stage-2, three
further types of errors continue to be reported. (28) gives some
token examples:
(28)
Genitive Case Errors |
Genitive Propositional Case Errors |
(Obj Prn in Genitive contexts) |
(Gen Prn in Nom Prn contexts) |
a. Me car (=my) (file 14: 2;7) |
j. My do it (=I) (file 22: 3;0) |
b. Where me car? (=my) (file 16: 2;8) |
k. My get it (=I) (file 21:3;0) |
c. Me pasta (=my) (file 18: 2;9) |
l. My wet (=I'm) (file 21) |
d. It's him hat (=his)(file 25: 3;6) |
|
e. Help him legs (=his) (file 25: 3;6) |
|
f. *Nose me (N+D =my) (file 19: 2;10) |
|
Prenominal/Pronominal
Gen Errors (files 18-19) |
g. Mine pasta (=my). h. Don't touch my!
(=mine). i. It my (=mine) |
(*A small set of case errors
were found to have Spec-final (N+D) orderings: their significance
(albeit few in number) might be linked to a potential Spec-final
option in the (preparameterized) grammar (UG)).
Similar to what happened regarding feature
deficits in IPs, such feature deficits within DPs can equally
result in erroneous case assignments with regards to Genitive
DP constructions. More specifically speaking, in maintaining that
Nominative Case is assigned by a finite [+Agr] feature in I, we
may similarly postulate that Genitive Case is assigned by a possessive
[+Agr] feature in D.[i] Therefore, by extending the same conditions to DP as we do with
respect to formal features of IP, we can assert that D must check-off
its formal features (if strong). In examples where correct Genitive
Case constructions are only optionally projected (as in the Optional-stage),
a tactic approach would be to state an underspecification for
that formal D-feature concerned (cf. Radford: class lectures,
'97). Consider the following DPs--some of which are Headed by
an "Agreement-less" Determiner:
(28')

(Regarding the instances of Prenominal/Pronominal
Genitive errors (cf. 28g-i), it seems likely that all the child
is doing here is wrongly extending the Pronominal version of Gen
case (mine) to Prenominal positions (e.g., Mine pasta vs.
It my, etc). Since both long/short versions are certainly
Genitive, there is nothing more to say).
Turning to Genitive My-Subject errors,
Radford (class lectures) suggests that My- Subjects could
be interpreted as Analogical Nominatives. That is to say,
they share the same feature checking processes (i.e., [+Agr] of
I) as do their Nominative I subject counterparts.[ii]
The view that My-Subjects are Analogical Nominatives also
accounts for the fact that they are rarely observed in the environment
of 3sg Inflection. Examples such as e.g., My does it
are unattested in my data. Without going into details here, the
basic premise of his proposal amounts to saying the following:
since the overall majority of Genitive Subjects produced by children
take the forms of either My or Her (instances of
productive use of all other forms e.g., *Our do it remain
largely unattested), a conclusion could be drawn that they are
not Genitives at all, but are rather Analogical Subjects (in the
case of My), and Objective Subjects (in the case of Her).
In light of Radford's position on My subjects, all instances
of My-subjects (as in example (i) above), would simply be analyzed
as a Nominative Subject--being checked by a [+Agr] feature in
I.
1.2.4 Pro
My data on Null Subjects (=Pros) further suggest
a Wexlerian (Optional Infinitive) approach: i.e., the distribution
of null subjects seems to follow quite straightforwardly from
the specification of I. Schütze (1997: 263) likewise concludes
that the licensing of Pro is independent of the feature responsible
for checking the case of the subject: Pros may be licensed upon
the alteration of [+/-Agr]. While GENs and Pros share possible
spell-out with [-Agr], NOMs and Pros share possible spell-out
with [+Agr]. The unique spell-out of Pro itself, regardless of
Agr, rather crucially depends on the absence of Tense contrasts
[-Tense] specification in I (referred to as TP). Thus, according
to Schütze, the combined specifications [-T,-/+Agr] may license
a Pro.[iii] In unambiguous [+Agr,+T] environments in my
data, null subjects don't seem to occur (Nb. Although I don't
wish to discount the possibility that (pragmatically-based)
Topic/Diary-drop structures may occur within finite
main clauses).[iv]
Syntactically-based Pros, on the other hand, seem exclusively
to occur among the total absence of I specification--i.e., the
unspecification of Agr (having to do with phi-features) and T--resulting
in [-Agr,-T]. (In fact, I have only one unambiguously Inflected
main clause with a Pro in all of my corpus and it seems that it
can be attributed to the Neg initial stage No (Pro) works
(=Daddy doesn't work)). In a similar vein with Wexler et al. (1996a,b)--who
attribute general Case assignment to the specification of Agr
(within a finite I) and not Tense--Hyams (1994), Hyams et al (1996a)
suggest that the following distributions of Pro may be accounted
for in a straightforward way. That is, Pro is licensed by the
apparent absence of an Agreement specification in I, and, in particular,
the absence of the number feature in D. Hyams (et al.) would therefore
predict that Pros occur within non-finite constructions only.
This correlation between Pro and unspecification of I is borne
out in my data.
(Pro in Spec-VP) One alternative
way of interpreting such early [-Agr,-T] Pro constructions is
to take the more parsimonious Structural Deficit view and
propose that Pro, in fact, occupies the Spec of VP--having nothing
whatsoever to do with a seemingly vacuous IP projection. Since
we already assume that Subjects start out in Spec-VP, a feasible
alternative to a Spec-IP structure would be to postulate that
Pro simply doesn't raise from out of Spec of VP into the functional
projection Spec of I. In adopting this stance, a clearer account
can be offered of why and how the unspecifications of Agr and
T do occur in early small clauses: mainly, the category that hosts
the features simply doesn't project.[v]
Consider some token [-Agr,-T] examples of Pro found in my data.
(29)
a. Pro (=I) kick the dog (file 4) |
e. Pro (=He) cook pasta (file 18) |
b. Pro (=I) want car (file 9) |
f. Pro (=She) want bottle (file 10) |
c. Pro (=He) eat a cake (file 19) |
g. Pro (=I) baby kick ((OV) file 11) |
d. Pro (=You) hurt my eye (file 23) |
h. Pro (=I) dog kick (OV) file 3) |
(29')

Moreover, the above VP-analysis
is consistent with the view that (big) PRO in adult "To"
infinitives is in Spec-VP and not in Spec-IP. This is deduced
from the notion that the cliticized wanna--(=want to) in
e.g., (I wan-na [VP (PRO) see you])--formation is
not blocked by the would be intervening PRO in Spec-IP
e.g. (*I wan-(PRO)-na [VP see you]) (see
Baltin 1995: 244 cf. Radford: ms1996). However, notwithstanding
the given child-to-adult continuity here regarding Pro in Spec-VP,
we must still develop a licensing mechanism for dealing with the
checking of Pro--be it in Spec-IP or Spec-VP.
In fact, a dual licensing of types
may be in order here. All missing arguments, including Null Subjects
at the lexical/thematic VP-stage (Stage-1), could, in principle,
be analyzed as Lexically Saturated items which are considered
implicit and thus void of syntactic projection (Radford 1990:
198 ff). In the case of Pros at the small clause VP-stage, there
are no (formal) syntactic conditions--hence, it is likely that
Pros are freely licensed to occur in any given environment for
this stage. Moreover, regarding the approximate target-grammar
(Stage-2), we could still follow Schütze (op. cit) and claim that
Spec-VP-Pros at the OI-stage are licensed by the outer
IP (TP)--similar to what we find with Exceptional Case Marking
(ECM). For the child here it may be much the same: although according
to my account, Pro would be licensed via the underspecification
of Agr and not T. Recall that in Schütze's model, T and Agrs
are fused under TP; hence, it becomes natural for Schütze to assume
that Pro is licensed by TP since it also encompasses AgrsP
as well. In our revised model where T and Agr project (independently)
their own Heads and perform separate tasks (viz., as witnessed
by the unitary function of the suffix "s" marking
T and not Agr (cf. 13)), we do not have the luxury of relying
entirely on T as the unique Head Node of the Functional Phrase.
Rather, for our purposes concerning a sole Pro licensing, we must
consider Agr. For example, in eliciting an AGR as a potential
licenser of Spec-VP-Pros (for the OI-stage), a natural
inference might be that Pro here is checked by a weak case feature
via attraction (and not movement) to the outside IP (=AGR), and
that such checking would be done under a non-fused Agr (cf. 15).
This might entail that a weak case feature (in AGR) licenses Pro
just as it is responsible for the default Accusative case in [-Agr,+T]
constructions e.g., Pro/Him goes, and [-Agr,-T] constructions
e.g., Pro/Him go, (cf. 16) at the OI-stage). This differs
with Schütze in that we now assume that Pro may, in theory, contain
a [+T] alongside a [-Agr] specification (Nb. Although Schütze
maintains that only the [-T] specification may actually trigger
Pros, he nevertheless asserts that the [-Agr] specification is
indeed a possible setting for its occurrence. Also, let us note
here that such a non-fused T(ensed) P(hrase) which only utilizes
a +Interpretable [+T] feature and none of the remaining formal
Agreement features may be considered as [-finite] if we wish to
define Finiteness as an Agreement relation (e.g., as in the checking
of +NOM case with +Finite. See note 15).
The Spec-IP-Pro analysis,
alternatively, would also be consistent with Chomsky's Pro
Theorem (in 33 below) that stipulates that the Functional
Head closest to the subject position remain empty. Following Pollock's
(1989) original model, in which T and AGR are projected as separated
Heads (and not fused), we may still abide by the conditions of
the Pro theorem by stating that if Tense is specified [+T], a
[-Agr] specification could still elicit Pro--where the nearest
Functional Head of AgrsP is void of lexical content:
(30)

Drawing attention to the distinctions
between a Pro in VP/IP, it is clear that the files presented above
suggest that Pro occurs within the Optional-Stage-2. Thus, we
are obliged (as discussed above) in projecting an abstract
IP [-Agr,-T] (at least for those files starting after file
8 since we have established that the Optional-Stage-2 has begun
by file 8). At this juncture, we have the option to either accommodate
the Pro-Spec-IP or VP models--whereas only the Spec-IP
version would seem to be in accordance with Chomsky's theorem
in (33). This alternative licensing of Pro-Spec-IP might
be equated with the child's treatment (in some instances) of the
default Acc case. Consequentially, this would suggest the following
remodeled AGR paradigm of Case for D and I:
(31)
Feature Specification
Subject Case Example
a. [-Agr] Head of I (main clause) => Default
ACC, Pro (Pro)/Him go-es
b. [+Agr] Head of I => NOM
He go-es
c. [-Agr] Head of D => Default
ACC Me car (=My car)
d. [+Agr] Head of D => GEN
My car
This also jibes with a study done
by Hyams (1994) where 25% of the verbs used with Pro structures
utilized a suffix "s" inflection and 56% utilized
a past "ed":
(32)
Pro with suffix "s"
Pro with past "ed" (ADAM 2;3-3;0).
e.g. Pro walks/is/am/are, etc Pro walked/goed/dropped,
etc.
Such findings go hand-in-hand with earlier discussions in this
section that sought to define the suffix "s"
as a Tense marker and not as an Agreement or dual Tense/Agreement
marker. Hyams accounts for such Pros among verbal inflections
by making the strong claim that the suffixes "s"
and "ed" in child syntax don't actually mark
Tense, but rather are Aspectual Participles agreeing with
their subjects (i.e., "s" and "ed"
mark participial agreement ("s" marking number
and not person). There seems to me to be no reason for such child-to-adult
Discontinuity regarding the inflections +s/+ed other
than, perhaps, to save the Pro theorem in (33):
(33)
Pro Theorem
(a) Pro must be ungoverned (Chomsky: 1981)
(b) Pro requires Null Case--i.e., checked by a Minimal INFL
(Chomsky and Lasnik: 1992)
Hyams asserts that the problem with having a specified T alongside
a Pro is that it breaks the condition in (33) shown in (34b) (Hyams
here shows overt verb raising to I):
(34)

However, if we were to adopt the Spec-VP-Pro analysis
for (34a) as discussed above (cf. 29'), then the condition in
(33) becomes rather meaningless and is thus no longer valid for
the VP stage: i.e., such a Pro in Spec-VP can't be governed by
a Functional Head in any case. In addition, if we assume the Pro-Spec-IP
analysis (cf.30), the conditions in (33) remain upheld. Radford
(contra Hyams) assumes here that such Pros (34b) are in fact null
subjects (diary-drops) that can occur in finite clauses. This
is deduced from the fact that children produce null subjects (in
main clauses) with unambiguous past tense forms (i.e., forms which
they don't use after have):
(35)
e.g. |
a. Ø Gave it mummy (Jem 2;0) (Radford, classs
lectures) |
|
b Ø Broke it (Adam 2;2) |
|
c. Ø Went to a theatre (Hannah 2;7) |
In this sense, since null subjects are being produced with unambiguous
[+T], there seems to be some evidence to suggest that the underspecification
of Agr [-Agr] might be involved--irrespective of the Tense-feature
specification. (As we shall see below, I attempt to expand the
distribution of Pros to finite clauses as well (dispensing with
the notion of diary drop for the OI-stage)--with the caveat that
the clauses aren't really finite at all, but are rather unspecified
for Finiteness and merely [+Tense] (See note 15). This, in fact,
attempts to unify the theory of Pro in child grammar: i.e., both
at the OI and VP stages, null subjects may either occur in non-finite
or finite (main clause) utterances: the former deriving Pro with
the specifications [-T,-Agr], the latter with [-Agr,+T]. Hence,
Non-Noms (e.g. Default Acc and Pros) may serve similar roles here:
i.e., their spell outs follow from the design of the syntax itself
in that forms lacking any case feature will be given the least
specific member of that paradigm (cf. Halle & Marantz: 1993).
(In a sense, if the child has, say retrieval problems with the
selection of a proper case, she now has two escape paths at her
disposal on which to fall back: Acc and Pro. This
is not to say that Pro must always function in this default capacity
(unlike Acc)--other syntactic factors, including semantic/pragmatics
or contextual information, may play a part.).
No instances of ProNull subjects in Wh-Questions or Subordinate
clauses with [-Agr] specification are borne out from this analysis.
(However, see Roeper & Rohrbacher (1994) for reports of Null
subjects in non-finite Wh-questions.[vi] Without further expanding on this comment, the rarity of Pros
among [-Agr, +/-T] subordinate clauses (e.g. I said *Pro/*him/he
want-ed one) could be accounted for in two ways. Firstly,
the absence of Pros here could be taken as a sign of the case
retrieval mastery by the child--simply speaking, by the time multi-constituent
subordinate clauses are acquired, the more primitive default
means of potential case spell out has long been abandoned. Furthermore,
a notion could be devised whereas once AGR features are correctly
specified in the main clause, all AGR specifications in the matrix
clause ensue. Secondly, we could resort to the Topic-drop account
that restricts Pros from occurring in clause medial positions.
Since the distributions of Pro and default Acc. are mutually assigned
by [-Agr], their manner of distribution becomes rather difficult
to make precise. For instance, the fact that the default Acc shows
more frequently than Pro may only demonstrates that the child
is utilizing the default in a productive manner, resorting to
Pro in exceptional cases.
In sum, what we are claiming here are two rather different accounts
for the licensing of Pro:
(i) Firstly, following Radford (1990), we consider Pros that
occur at the VP Stage-1 (the stage that manifest a total underspecification
of I) to be lexically saturated Null NPs (np) which are
not constrained by syntactic conditions. In this sense, Pro is
free to occur within any environment--with the added stipulation
that all crucial semantic information is restored at LF.
(ii) Secondly, at the Optional-Infinitive Stage-2 (with the onset
of T/Agr underspecifications viz., starting from our file 8 onwards),
Pros could be alternatively licensed by an empty or underspecified
AGR--in accordance with (33b) which states that only a Minimal
INFL can check Null Case (we take underspecification of Agr here
as constituting a minimal INFL). This results in the possible
pairing of Pro with an Inflected V for Tense. The notion that
Pros could remain in Spec-VP throughout remains a topic of debate--nothing
in my account seems to hinge on this distinction and so I leave
it open to question.
1.2.5 Tense Revisited
The features of INFL, as already mentioned above, are intricately
connected to Case via Agreement--resulting in a myriad of possible
hybrid sentences depending upon which specific INFL feature manifest
(as in (10') above demonstrating +Agr/-Tns). The main issues regarding
INFL seem to me to be centered around notions of Language Specifics
as opposed to Language Universals (e.g., Chomsky: 1995). Almost
all researchers agree--upon one thing that is--that the emergence
of INFL (particularly Tense since Agr may be invisibly marked for
English) is paramount in importance for those attempting to locate
and /or describe early language separation among bilinguals (cf.
Meisel). Whereas the former section was mainly devoted to Agreement
(having to do with Case assignment), this section is particularly
devoted to looking at the sole distribution of Tense. (3
sg suffix "s") Overt Tense suffix "s"
appears productive (i.e., free from any semi-formulaic interpretation)
late in my English Data (file 23: 3;2). Once we dispose of
ambiguous finite utterance counts (e.g., I go, I cry, etc.)
that may mark null [ ø] tense, we are left with a seemingly
small number of early Tensed "s" forms (recall
that we considered it safe to regard ambiguous finite clauses as
[-Tense] at least at the early stages). Token examples of later
unambiguous 3sg/present [+finite] constructions are given in (36)
below *(disregarding early Is+N constructions thought to
be formulaic in nature (note 7) (restated from Table 1.6 above):
(36)
Table 1.9 |
Token Examples: +S (Files 24-25) |
|
A man works a tree. Baby awakes. |
3sg/Pres +S: Obligatory Contexts |
That one works. Baby cries. It hurts |
Age |
+S |
It rains. Elephant eats a monkey. |
|
My Barney works. Nicolas no eats. |
2;3-3;1 *9/69 (0%) (restricted
to copula Is+N) |
3;2-3;6 72/168 (43%) (verbal
+s begins) |
(36')

(Copulas) A second source of possible
early Finite constructions appears in the form of Copula verbs.
Examples include (37a-g) for Correct usage, and (37h-n) for Incorrect:
(37)
Correct Copula Use |
Incorrect Copula Use |
a. I am three (file 24) |
h. Here are me (file 23) |
b. I am a cowboy (file 24) |
i. Where's you? (file 24) |
c. I am not (file 24) |
j. Here is me (file 24) |
d. Here are you (file 23) |
k. You is no nice (file 24) |
e. Where are you? (file 24) |
l. This is your books (file 25) |
f. You are dead (file 25) |
m. Here you am (file 25) |
g. They are bad guys (file 25) |
n. Where you is? (file 24) |
All instances of correct Copula constructions (37a-g)
are to be analyzed as in (7') above--where Aux/Copula verbs are
initially generated under a VP (for thematic purposes) and involve
(V-to-I) raising to the Head of IP. However, one interesting note
about the structures in which copulas show incorrect subject-agreement
is that they appear to have Objective/Acc(usative) Subjects. That
is, not one token example of Incorrect Copula constructions was
found to occur with a Nominative Subject. This might be interpreted
in a number of ways. Foremost, in examples (37i,j,n) the Pronouns
and Wh-elements Here and Where might take on the
role of 3sg superficial Subjects (the Wh-element either
being base-generated or derived) resulting in the verb's 3sg inflection
(with examples like 37h posing a potential problem).[vii] In addition, if Is marks present tense [+T], then You
in examples Where's you? (i), You is no nice (k),
Where you is? (n), would, theoretically, be Objective [-Agr]--on
the grounds that if they were [+Agr] Nominative, we would expect
the verb to inflect for agreement (and hence be Are):
(37')

The resulting Incorrect Copula constructions seem to rely on
a confusion between the feature matching of the [-Agr] Acc. Subject
and the [+T] INFL--where Agr seems to be unspecified. Again, the
observation that Nom
Case is altogether absent from such constructions reinforces
the Optional Stage Hypothesis.
(Past "ed" and irregulars) Use of suffix
"ed" and irregulars was sporadic even up
until the last recording. While irregulars started to be productively
used at around File 12, it is not until File 23 that we record
the first productive use of "ed". The relatively
late onset of the past tense rule "add-ed", as
compared to their irregular counterparts, favors the notion that
the two processes may be stored very differently in the brain
(see note 26). Consider the token examples below that indicate
a [+T] specification:
(38)
Suffix "ed" |
Irregular past |
a. What happened the door? (file 23) |
g. I did it (file 12) |
b. I opened it (file 24) |
h. I ate (file12) |
c. I killed the bug (file 25) |
i. Cat ate the cake (file 19) |
d. I liked it (file 25) |
j. I got it ( file 19 [+past,-part] ) |
e. I wanted it (file 25) |
k.We came back (file 25) |
f. I said no! (file 25) |
|
(38')

These findings could be interpreted to suggest that the suffix
"ed" comes on-line extremely late in the data owing
to its rule-based nature. More specifically, since the
"ed" past tense is a result of a morphological
rule (which can often be overgeneralized e.g., I wented/goed/hitted),
it may require more time for the rule to assert itself into the
morphosyntax. The Irregular forms however, being non-ruled-based,
are pulled directly from out of the lexicon (in one chunk) and
hence, have a scheduled on-line time similar to lexical
items.[viii] In
this sense, one may very well find at the one/two-word lexical
stage utterances containing irregulars: e.g., Daddy did,
Me done, All-done, (np) ate, etc.
(Aux/"Dummy Do" Insertion) A brief
look at the INFL data on Aux/Dummy Do-insertions suggests
that semantically light verbs (such as a raised Do)
are acquired fairly late in the data--with no instances of aux/modals
can, may, will, need, have
in the total corpus. In early examples of Negative constructions,
(which are unambiguous instances of obliged Do-insertions)
no examples of Do-insertions appear.
(39)
Non Do-Insertion
a. I know (=I don't know x8) (file 8)
b. No cook (=I don't cook) (file 12)
c. No cut the train (=Don't cut the train) (file16)
d. What you want? (file 24)
e. I no have glasses (file 24)
f. All little boys no like me (file 24)
g. You eat? (file 24)
The lack of light verbs raising here demonstrates that
the child relies on a certain amount of semantics for verbal projection--since
light verbs, aux/modals are formal categories which lack any real
semantic material, the child at the early Lexical/OI-stages may
choose to leave them unprojected (see Schütze 1997:) for a broader
discussion on the topic where sufficient relevant data is used).
1.3 Final Remarks
In sum, a collective picture begins to emerge supporting the
notion that unambiguous Finites and Inflection--both being properties
of a projected IP--appear fairly late in the data. More specifically,
the overall conclusion which the findings reported lead to favors
the notion that aspects of Inflectional-Morphology,
in Language Acquisition, is on the most part of a protracted nature.
The data indicate that a two-stage developmental process of language
acquisition is at hand: (i) A Stage-1 Prefunctional
Stage (keeping to Radford's original Thesis, cf. Radford:
1990) where No-Functional Categories are present--ultimately
resulting in the observed errors found with respect to Case,
Agreement/Tense and (ii) A Stage-2 Optional Inflection/Infinitive
stage[ix] (cf. Wexler's Hypothesized
Optional-Infinitive stage) where we find the (unstable)
emergence of the Functional Categories IP/CP, along with the characteristics
of Underspecification/Optionality. Moreover, the early emergence
of DP (within the VP-stage) was analyzed as having Objective (default)
case. This strained any attempt toward maintaining a general D-I
correlation.
Following Radford & Galasso (ibid), the data presented in
this chapter has pointed to an interesting (and previously unreported)
symmetry between the general developments of Inflective properties:
viz., Subject+Verb constructions on the one hand and Possessive+
Nouns constructions--both constructions showed symmetric-chronological
developmental patterning of Inflective markings for 3per/sg +S
and possessive 'S (respectively). Again, such data clearly
indicated a 2-stage model of acquisition: (i) a No-Inflection-Stage-1,
& (ii) a Optional-Inflection-Stage-2 (Stage-3
marking the complete mastery of the target grammar). (Postscriptum)
Though I am fully aware that some researchers may wish to analyze
the proposed first stage of language development (=stage-1 of
my data) as an obligatory Optional Infinitive stage (albeit
a first stage where the features of INFL are always present but
never specified), I believe, this is hastily concluded. The data
thus far presented in this chapter, as well as the previous chapter,
when taken as a whole, clearly point to a Two-Stage linguistic
development--indicating distinctions between Lexical vs.
Functional classifications of language acquisition. It
goes without saying that the majority of Data used by those working
in developmental linguistics today largely come from the same
R. Brown studies (1973) taken from the compilation of The CHILDES
Data-base--a collection of corpora which would seem to cast a
favorable light on an initial (stage-1) OI-stage (see Stromswold
in this chapter). Hence, reasons to collect a more exhaustive
Data-Base are more important then ever, as we continue to grapple
with all the complexities that language acquisition has to offer.
I believe that this corpus has reiterated the classic points initially
made by the Maturation/Structure-Building School, and, in so doing,
has rightly returned the burden of proof to those who esteem toward
Strong Continuity models of child and adult syntax.)
<<
Back to Index
[i]
This ties up the notion that all formal/functional categories, whether
it be IP, DP, or CP, are defined in relation to their strong vs
weak features--substantive items (lexical Verbs, Nouns, Adj. etc.)
cannot be defined in such a manner: it is rather meaningless to
speak of lexical categories as having strong vs. weak features.
[ii] Radford considers the idea that the 1st per Pronoun is of the
form Stem+affix:
Me/My/I= /m+i/, /m+aI/, / ø+aI / so that the
My subject is in fact a nominative I with an improper stem. This
suggestion is however only one means to account for My subjects
in child syntax. Another possibility would be that genitive case
is checked by [+Agr] Head--either in D or I in the child syntax
(unlike in adult syntax where Genitive must be checked by a Nom
[+Agr] Head. In this alternative sense, the child wrongly assumes
that only a [+Agr] is needed to check Genitive case--regardless
of the Head type. The adult syntax is specific: (i) [+Agr]
by a Nominal (D) Head checks Genitive; (ii) [+Agr] by a INFL
Head checks Nominative case.
[iii]
Schütze (ibid: 188 fn.1) replaces Agr with an Accord relation here
to clarify the meaning of [-Agr]--since nothing hinges on this distinction
with respect to my own analysis, I have taken the liberty to continue
using Agr for sake of continuity.
[iv] One
could make an argument that diary style speech (Diary drop) is pragmatically
based and should not be analyzed in the same manner as syntactic
PROs. In order for the child to create a diary drop structure, the
child must have special awareness of the context and meaning of
intent. It seems plausible to me that young children lack such awareness
and that consequent null subjects generally fall in the class of
PRO.
[v] Again,
the VP analysis here is not so straightforward. Recall our dilemma
faced earlier (cf. 10e-g) regarding the reasoning behind projecting
an abstract IP [-Agr,-T], etc.
[vi] Guilfoyle
and Noonan (1988), Radford (1990: 132) have proposed a VP-Adj(unct)
analysis for Wh-questions with PRO subjects. In this sense, the
Spec of VP may be filled in by a Non-cased nominal, Default Acc,
or PRO (a, b, c, respectively):

[vii]
Here are me raises the question of what specification Are
carries. If we assume that it simply specifies [+T], then we have
two entries for [+T] ( Is, Are) causing overlap contra principles
of Economy. Radford (pc) has devised a story which suggests that,
in the case that an (+interpretable) default Acc case subject (subject-first
person) is used with an (-interpretable) INFL (verb-second person),
the child creates an anti-crash strategy whereby she only
erases the (-interpretable) INFL features, leaving the Acc subject
feature to survive the derivation even though the INFL features
are mis-matched. In the example of I are, the child cannot
repair the mis-match since the (-interpretable) Nom case can only
be erased when the (-interpretable) Agr features of the subject
match those of INFL. The example Here you am (m)
(= you (+Nom)) eludes such a story and may only
be accounted for by resorting to Pronoun switching (cf. Chiat) whereby
the child switches the intended pronoun with that of the interlocutor--( e.g.,
Here you am=Here I am).
[viii]
See Marcus, Clahsen et al. (1996) for their psychological studies
that support the view that regular vs. irregular morphologies are
stored quite differently in the brain.
[ix] Radford
(cf. ms Radford et Galasso) makes reference to this observed optional
stage-2 as an Optional-Inflection stage--whereas, contra
Wexler, OIs refer to tense/finiteness, the term here applies to
Inflection.
|
|