Non-count Noun Determiners:
Where is the Feature?
Joseph Galasso
joseph.galasso@csun.edu
California State University, Northridge
2001
This paper attempts to locate and account for a specific D-feature,
shared only by a handful of (D)eterminers, which seems to allow
for the modification of Non-count Nouns via a Spec/Head/Comp
relationship within the DP. We examine evidence in connection
with a class of Determiners that leads to the assumption that
syntactic constraints may restrict some items to certain expression.
In examining the role the Determiner plays in projecting Non-count
Nominal expressions, we conclude by saying that one can no longer
adhere to previously held notions of a pure category class of
lexical items, particularly among the functional categories,
and an effort is made toward applying a 'finer-grained' analysis
to the items themselves, placing a greater emphasis on inherent
grammatico-semantic features internal to the lexical item itself.
This approach coincides with recent work in Feature Theory as
understood in Chomsky (1995).
0. Overview
There is no question that certain Determiners do impose tight restrictions
on the selection of Nouns they can modify. Regarding non-count noun
determiners, these restrictions are syntactic in nature and relate
to grammatical number. Non-count Nouns, their number feature, labeled
herein as [-COUNT], are said to be 'inherently singular' in number-i.e.,
they are nouns that never take the plural [+s] e.g., (furniture/*furnitures)
(asterisk* marks a syntactically ill-formed sentence). Following
this up, we can stake out early on in our discussion three types
of selective determiners:
(a) Determiners like The which can modify any kind
of noun [+/-COUNT]
(b) Determiners like Enough which can modify [+Plural]
and non-count nouns
(c) Determiners like An/A which can modify only a singular
[-Plural] count noun.
These restrictions can be readily expressed in broad terms, showing
the selectiveness of number sensitive Determiners toward their Noun
complements: viz., (i) the determiner A modifies a singular
count Noun (A chair/*chairs/*furniture), (ii)
Much modifiers a singular non-count noun (Much furniture/*chair/*chairs),
(iii) Several modifies a plural count noun (Several
chairs/*chair/*furniture), and (iv) More modifies
either a plural count noun or a singular mass noun (more chairs/furniture/*chair).
As stated above, non-count nouns have no 'plural' due to their inherent
singular meaning-hence, they can't be pluralized. However, as we
shall see in this paper, such Non-count Nouns may be sensitive to
number agreement. The distribution of such determiners has come
to be captured by the following binary feature distinction [+/-COUNT].
For example, the D(eterminer) Several in example (iii) would contain,
as one part of its lexical properties, a grammatical feature [+PLURAL]
which would specify that only such nouns with the matching nominal
f-feature [+PLURAL] could serve as a possible complement of the
D, as borne out in the following sentence: I have [DP [D several]
[N books/*book/*furniture]] in my room. More specifically,
there are only a handful of determiners that can modify Non-count
Nouns (e.g., furniture/butter/milk/salt/sand etc.). They are identified
herein as the following class: Determiners the, this, that,
no, some, a bit of, little, less, much, more, most, all as
well as an overlap of polarity determiners which form Question or
Negative constituents any, and some (see §4). All of the aforementioned
determiners may modify Non-count Nouns: e.g.,
(0) John
has the/no/some/a-bit-of/less/little/much/more/most/all furniture.
Is
there any/some furniture? (Polarity Question)
There
isn't any furniture (Polarity Negation).
Many of these same determiners share the potential of being either
contrastive or non-contrastive in other distributional paradigms.
In this short paper, we look at recent developments in Feature-Checking
Theory (as outlined in Chomsky 1995) and see if
(i) an already established common feature might be deduced
in accounting for the highly selective
nature of their Non-count-Noun modification, or if no common feature
can be drawn out,
(ii) to devise a separate feature which is semantically
based on referential properties which may
show some sensitivity toward number.
1. Introduction: Feature Theory
In what could be seen as a natural extension of morphologically
driven subcategorization features, the internal mechanism of features
which underpin specific lexical items has now become the playing
field for much of what goes on in syntactic theory. Whereas a certain
amount of achievement was sustained early on by such traditional
categorical-based models (i.e., word-level or lexical level
subcategories), efforts to account for seemingly idiosyncratic distinctions
among individual word items themselves failed. For example, categorical-based
models classify words in a general class according to parts-of-speech,
(noting that a word such as joke would take a plural [S]
(joke-s) => word class: [+NOUN] [-VERB]), but not the
word jokingly, (*jokingly-s) => word class:
[-NOUN] [+ADVERB]). Although the models suggested that there had
to be something in the internal make-up of the general lexical items
(per se) that either allowed or disallowed certain types of inflections
and/or complements, no real attempt was made to account for differing
behaviors and distributions of particular words of the same class
(the topic of the this paper). In other words, while a category-based
model provided a broad description of the bundle of words which
made up a category (N, V, Adj, Adv), it provided no outlet for describing
crucial differences found between words within the same category:
e.g., traditional notions of count vs. non-count nouns, etc. There
seems to be no way to handle the distinction of the two nouns without
separating them into two-categories (mass and count). While
the two-category approach would certainly capture this refined difference
between the two, it would do so at the expense of abandoning the
larger and more important 'Noun' word-class similarity between them.
What seems to be needed in this case are finer gained models which
(i) divert lexical analyses somewhat away from the actual
word-class itself (but not at the expense of the class), and rather
(ii) examine the possible arrangement of the precise lexical
internal features (i.e., subcategorial features) which factor in
such differences between words of the same class.
On the heels of such analyses, a methodological paradigmatic shift
occurred which sought to define 'word-bundles' as 'feature-bundles'.
More recently, under Chomsky's vision of a Minimalist Program for
linguistics (MP), much has been written about the precise make-up
of these individual (+/-BINARY) features (semantically and/or morphologically
based)[1].
Early explicit calls for this separation between the category item
and its features, under MP assumptions, takes place when Chomsky
(1995: 35) states that certain features of Nouns, (termed phi-features
or f-features: person, number, gender), define, to a large degree,
the items' scope of selection. In essence, Chomsky's 1994 version
of Merger Theory does away with fixed sets of labels for functional
projections CP, IP, DP as provided by UG, and rather adopts the
position that functional projections are feature bundles-their properties
determined by their head-features. Exciting new proposals have been
put forward suggesting how such features should be independently
defined, and how they might even be extracted from out of the word
itself: viz., zero allomorphic features which exist in analogy only,
despite absence of phonological visibility (as shown in the structure
in (3)), and conversely, overt Tense/Agr Inflections whose features
may even be extracted from its lexical Verb-base stem as in feature
percolation to IP (i.e., raising in English). To make matters more
concrete, Nouns have two sub-classes: traditionally termed common
nouns and proper nouns. Using the present terminology herein,
we would state that a specific grammatical feature in the Noun signals
this distinction, labeled here as [+/-COMMON]. It is this precise
Noun feature which renders a given modifying Determiner acceptable
or not: noting the sentences e.g., (i) Do you like to visit
the *New York/America? [=Proper Noun], (ii) Do
you like to visit the capital/ocean/city? [=Common Noun].
What is happening here is that Common Nouns can freely be modified
by determiners The, whereas Proper Nouns cannot. (Note
that if one so desired to treat proper nouns as having common noun
features, such as the feature [+/-NUMBER] in that more than one
New York may exist in the mind-one for the rich and one for the
poor-then it would be conceivable to state e.g., The New York
that I know..., etc.. The use of The here conjures
up referentials of singular vs. plural number. (This notion of Reference
will come up again in the context of Non-count Nouns later in this
paper). Under this Feature-Matrix approach, both the specific lexical
features embedded in the lexical item as well the lexical item itself
partake in the particulars of syntax. Consequences of this new approach
are now being played out regarding Child Language Acquisition (cf.,
Clahsen's (1994) Lexical Learning Hypothesis)[2]. In the context of child language
acquisition, Clahsen (following Chomsky) states that-there is
no fixed set of labels for functional projections CP, IP,..provided
by UG; rather, functional projections are features of bundles, and
their properties are determined by their head feature (ibid:
6). Questions such as how such features interact within certain
syntactic spec-head-comp relations and configurations have become
the cornerstone of MP: notably, how such features interact among
varying items among functional categorial phrases DP, CP, and IP
2. Determiners and Non-count Nouns: Three Conjectures
This paper attempts to locate and account for a specific feature
shared by only a handful of Determiners (Det) that seems to allow
Non-count [-COUNT] Nouns to sit as its complement. Determiner Referentials
the/a, this/that, these/those; Genitive my/your,
his/her, our/their; as well as Cardinal numbers one/two/three...,
Quantifiers no/some/less/little/more/many/every/a lot
of all of which make-up a single broad ranging functional category
which predominantly serves to introduce a Noun (N) or Noun Phrase
(NP)[3].
However, as indicated above, there is also a wide range of specificity
that accompanies such Determiners which has often gone unnoticed
in the literature. Regarding the number feature in particular, it
immediately becomes clear that a certain sub-class of determiners
are sensitive to number-Sing(ular) and Pl(ural). Consider the following
examples below:
(1)
Singular
Plural
a. This [-pl]
c. These [+pl]
b. That [-pl] d.
Those [+pl]
a' *This books/This book
c' . *These book/ These books
b'. *That books/That book d'
*Those book/ Those books
(2) a. A [-pl]
b.
The [+/-pl]
a'. *A
books/book b'.
The books/book
(* marks ungrammaticality. The feature [-pl] (minus plural) simply
indicates that the determiner A exclusively selects for +present.)
There are many more examples where these come from. The point here
is that Determiners certainly do hold certain sensitivity to number
[singular vs. plural]. The next step is to examine a class of DP
complement Nouns which likewise hold a certain sensitivity toward
number, mainly Non-count Nouns (often termed Mass Nouns):
(i.e., furniture/sand/salt/butter/mile etc.). Whereas Count Nouns
refer to 'concrete' objects that are considered to be separate entities
(i.e., +Individuatable), Non-Count Nouns/Mass Nouns refer
to possibly more abstract and 'non-concrete' substances that are
inseparable (i.e., -Individuatable). Non-Nouns cannot take
certain determiners as their Specifiers that would otherwise specify
and project the Head-feature of number onto the Noun. Consider the
following examples below illustrating the relevant Head-features
on the Determiner (=> [D'[D-Head]] ) in association with a non-count
noun complement such as the non-count noun furniture:

Clearly, in addition to positing that all the above determiners
fall into a general Det-class, there must be an additional property
that distinguishes the feature (indicated by the Head-Feature zero
allomorph Ø) of number sensitivity. At first glance, it seems
that the tale-tell feature lies somewhere between the Definiteness
and Indefiniteness of The and A (4a/e) insofar
that A is sensitive to number (the article A must
take a singular Noun) and The is not (cf. 2). (There is
something to the notion that Determiners that can modify Non-count
Nouns typically tend to be Indefinite). On first try, a story could
be devised suggesting that Definite The may enter into
a Non-count Nouns relationship by virtue that it holds a weak sensitivity
to number-this would be apparent from its selective scope found
in (2b). The conjecture would go as follows:
(5) Conjecture #1: 'The wrong one'
Since Determiner The seems to bear no number sensitivity,
count as well as non-count nouns can function as its complement.
This is borne out in (4e). As a consequence, the determiner A-sensitive
to number insofar that it must select for a [N, -Plural] complement-becomes
illicit. In this conjecture, it would be this number sensitivity
factor that would render *A furniture illicit.
However, this cannot be the whole story. Recall, not only is A
sensitive to number, but so too are the demonstratives this/that,
these/those as shown in (1). Moreover, number sensitive can't
be the whole story since the Determiner Little seems to
modify inherently Singular Non-Count Nouns despite its inherently
Plural properties: (cf. John has little toys (=a
small about of) [+Pl], vs. *John has little toy [-Pl] vs.
John has little furniture in his room). Hence, a potentially
strong uniformity view that Non-count Noun Determiners all have
no inherent number to speak of it simply wrong. Let's flesh this
out by taking a closer look at just how these number sensitive determiners
play out here. Well, where one would predict ungrammatical structures
for the above Demonstratives Non-count Nouns, owing to their apparent
sensitivity to number, they are nonetheless acceptable in (6).
(6) a. This/that furniture is ours.
It appears that a still finer grained selective measure must be
involved. Recall, that Conjecture #1 states that The is
acceptable precisely because it doesn't care about the number-feature
on its complement: cf. The book vs. The books. (It would appear
that The contains some form of default setting for number
and so is indifferent toward the feature, hence, both are permitted).
If we take the same line of reasoning with e.g., this/that
and these/those (since they too are sensitive to number
with regards to +/-Plurality) we would wrongly predict the former's
acceptability in (6) to be ungrammatically marked, but it is well
formed. Moreover, recollect that it just can't be as simple as saying
Singular Determiners select Non-count Nouns because, as we have
already attested, the [-Pl] Determiner A doesn't work (cf. 4a),
and in addition we have apparent possible counter example as seen
in the following sentences (cf.4g/h): (e.g., I have enough/more/some
*table/tables/*chair/chairs/furniture). Certainly, the determiners
enough, more and some seem to exclusively select for either (i)
plural count noun or (ii) non-count noun. What is going
on here? Well, as it turns out, we must refine our story somewhat
to account for the possible selection of such apparent number sensitive
determiners as this/that over these/those etc. toward non-count
nouns (Conjecture #2 below).
(7) Conjecture #2: 'The partially right one'
In order to account for the number selection of determiners,
we have to look to one additional selective property of determiners-namely,
the subcategorial feature of Referential-Det. [+R/-Q] vs.
Quantifying-Det. [-R/+Q].
(i)
Determiners [+R] make-up the list e.g., the/this/that/these/those/my/our,
and are responsible for the denoting reference of nouns.
(ii)
Determiners [+Q] make-up a semantic gradient list (basically quantifying
a semantic scope of 'None-to-all'): e.g., A/no one/some,
two/any, (a)couple/a bit of, (a)few/little,
none/much, many/more, several/most every/less
All determiners in (i) make-up a class of R(eferentials),
and, except for the determiners these/those marked for
[+Plural] number, can by default modify non-count nouns. Regarding
the demonstrative determiners (this/that, these/those),
although they make-up what is often referred to as system morphemes
(i.e., functional categories), they nonetheless share a general
deictic function which may be seen as highly lexical in nature (hence,
their [+R] status). Demonstratives are generally deictic in that
they are ostensive and 'point directly' so that their values are
determined locally and are context specific. The determiners in
(ii) are responsible for denoting a somewhat less ostensive
role: a sub-class of these less deictic Q(uantification)
nouns promote number sensitivity toward D which will come to affect
the selection of Non-count nouns. (Note above that the Determiner
A has been reorganized as a [+Q] Determiner, and not an
[+R] Determiner, for reasons having to do with its semantics of
quantity-the indefinite determiner A semantically shows gradient
opposition towards some, unlike the which only
pertains to referential aspects). Out of the Determiner [+R] class,
all default [+singular/-pl] Determiners the and my/our
etc. can select a non-count mass noun precisely because-
(i) their general notion of referentiality doesn't place
any condition on number, and among the [+R] determiners this/that/these/those,
only this/that apply because
(ii) the feature [+singular,-pl] acts somewhat as a default
setting which closely correlates with the conditions placed on
inherently singular non-count nouns.
So, in a limited sense, number sensitivity does apply, but only
after we have substantially sifted through an entire range of other
D-feature specificity. It may be that core Referential Determiners
don't include as part of their D-feature specificity the notion
of number. (Hence, the grammatical function of number found in determiners
this vs. these may have more to do with Agreement
features on the Head of D and not Referential features per se)-the
sole semantic function of Det.[+R] is to express entities (e.g.,
objects and concepts). Out of the Det.[+Q] class above, (and the
list is by no means exhaustive), it becomes apparent that only select
(underlined second order) grades of quantifiers can take non-count
nouns: specifically-
(i) only the second determiner of each gradient pair
can modify non-count nouns: (e.g., -/no, -/some, -/a bit of,
-/much, -/more, etc.). Why this is will be briefly addressed
in §§3, 4).
All this leads to our third and final conjecture:
(8) Conjecture # 3: 'The correct one'
The following rules apply to the acceptability of determiners with
non-count nouns:
(a). Any [-Pl] Determiner that is marked for [+R] can select a
Non-count noun: their semantic referential properties place no
conditions on number.
(b). Only second order gradient Determiners marked for [+Q] can
select Non- count nouns.
It is at this point that we can now rightly shift out focus of
attention to more overriding problem of defining exactly what these
'second order' gradient determiners are.
3. Gradient Determiners
In one of Eric Lenneberg's later classic papers[4], an early attempt was made-using
what would become a modern day linguistic framework-to sort through
the convolution of semantic grades of class determiners. One of
the first claims to be made was that an ordered overlap exists in
certain determiners. For example, the semantic scopes of the paired
determiners e.g. a couple vs. a few are said to
overlap-the prime determiner a couple merging with the
next semantically nearest determiner a few bringing about
semantic extension. That is, since their semantic fields do not
distinctly intrude upon the other, an overlap of sorts prevailed
(cf. 7(ii)). He later went on in the paper to discuss notions
of how verbs such as add, join, increase, etc. were quite
transparently related to singularity and plurality (Ibid: 31). This
early observation that a unified part-of-speech, such as the structure-class
category of determiner, could take on very different selective properties,
I believe, was pioneering work of his day; his working insights
capture what I believe to be the central core of Feature Theory
within the Minimalist Framework (Chomsky 1995). One of the most
striking descriptions come with Lenneberg's statement that there
may be hidden (binary-driven) common denominators behind words.
Exercising etymology, he goes on to suggest that the binary distinction
between the determiners one vs. none stems from
a more robust feature of [Existence] versus [Non-Existence],
and from out of this proto-feature derived the feature specificity
of [+/-Quantifying] whereas the concept of existence is
neutral with respect of quantity-viz., the state of being (Existence)
applies to one as well as to many.
Today, it is not too far off the mark to suggest that this is what
is exactly happening with regards to Feature Theory (see Chomsky
1995 Ch.4). As was shown above, it is no enough to simply categorize
words into general Lexical or Functional categories (e.g., Nouns
vs. Verbs, Determiners vs. Complementizers, etc.
respectively). But what one needs is a finer grained measure to
spell out the precise features of such items in order to account
for their distributional properties. We certainly would fail here
if we were to say that all determiners could equally select for
Non-count Nouns randomly. Similarly, so too would we fail if we
were to stipulate for only a select handful of determiners, paying
no attention to the specific grammatical features of the words themselves,
and only acting on prescriptive impulse driven by traditionally
broad division of the class item. (In our case of determiners, this
would mean by the presciption of say possessive determiners my/her,
or cardinal number determiners as in one/two, etc.). This
is not a viable option. As we quickly discovered, the selective
properties of the determiners to select for Non-Count Nouns are
broad and sweep well across the whole spectrum of class determiners-choosing
one while skipping another in apparent randomness. Turning next
to specific feature specification among Determiners, we can begin
to make some headway and construct an account for the permissiveness
of some over others, turning randomness into a coherent theory.
4. Polarity Items
Edward Klima (1964) first proposed the notion that certain items
or expressions contained an inherent formal feature referred to
as an affective polarity feature. These Determiners (DPs)
that hold such features are restricted to occurring within the scope
of an appropriate affective constituent. One well understood polarity
has to do with negative, interrogative and conditional
constituents. (What we would like to add here to this association
is a number sensitivity expression constituent as having
a bearing on the distribution of D(P) and Non-Count Nouns. (See
(12) below). Consider the syntax of the Quantifier Determiner Any
along with its compounds any-one, any-thing, etc.
(keeping in mind that these compounds can be reduced to their inherent
D+N constructs-
cf., [DP [D
The/this/some-/any-] [N one]] ). There are two
different grammatico-semantic types of uses for Any here: one as
a Univ(ersal) Q(uantifier) with a meaning similar to Every,
the second as an Exis(tential) Q(uantifier) with a meaning
similar to that of Some.
Consider the following uses:
(9) a.
Any (=every) batsman could have hit that pitch. (=Univ-Q)
b.
Are there any (=some) players left to bat? (=Exist-Q)
Regarding the subtle semantico-grammatic feature here, it turns
out that it is only the Existential version of Any [Exist-Q]
(and not the Universal Any) that seems to be allowed to
co-exist with negative (as well as interrogative or conditional)
constructs:
(10) a.
He hasn't hit any-thing (=some-thing) all game. (Exist-Negative)
b.
*He hasn't hit any-thing (=every-thing) all game. (Univ-Negative)
c.
He has hit *any-thing/some-thing today.
Following this carefully, it seems that we can demonstrate here
that even within the same lexical item, in this case the determiner
Any, there may be two opposing features that are sufficiently
different to bring about the disparity in distribution-a subtlety
that could only be pinned down to one specific feature within the
same lexical item. What we believe regarding the distribution and
modification of non-count nouns is that Exist-Q determiners have
an inherent quasi-formal property, the affective Polarity feature
being but one manifestation, and, as a consequence, notions of formal
checking enter into the picture (see §8). It will be our claim
herein that the formal feature, be it linked to a kind of polarity
expressions or number sensitivity expression linked to Agreement,
is responsible for the particulars of distributions found among
the D+N configuration of Non-count Nouns: i.e, only those determiners
which can exclusively modify Non-count nouns are to be associated
with the polarity number sensitivity expressions.
Taking this one step further, consider the example of the distributional
properties of the determiner any, and compound anyone
(as opposed to some, someone) below:
(11)
The Determiner Any
a. Is there any bread on the table?
b. *There is any bread on the table.
c. Is anyone going to the meeting?
d. *Anyone is going to the meeting
e. I don't believe anyone will say anything
f. *I believe anyone will say anything.
g. If anyone should ask why, say nothing!
h. *Anyone should ask why.
|
|
The Determiner Some
i. Is there some bread on the table.
j. There is some bread on the table?
k. Is someone going...?
l. Someone is going...
m. I don't believe someone will...
n. I believe someone will say...
o. If someone should say...
p. Some should say...
|
The meaning of the two determiners is basically the same. Notwithstanding
close semantic overlap (as Lenneberg suggested), in the first example
(a/b) any can only occur in the interrogative sentence,
as opposed to the declarative sentence, whereas the determiner some
is unrestricted in its distributions (cf. 10c). The restricted distribution
of any (in complementary distribution to some)
is said to stem from the notion that the lexical item any
contains, as one of its many sub-category components, an Existential-Quantifier
D-feature. This quantifier feature is a Polarity Feature
that renders certain expressions illicit (viz. only negation, interrogative
and condition expressions are permitted, as cited above). Note that
regarding this particular feature specification, the determiners
some and any line-up in opposition to each other.
However, as cited in §1 above in the case of Non-count Noun
distributions, they both would share in the same distribution, being
triggered by an identical D-feature: (cf. Is there
any furniture/milk/butter? and/or Is there some furniture/milk/butter?).
In order to tackle the 'any-some' paradox, clearly an added
D-feature has to be employed to capture the essence of this affective
constituency.
5. The 'Any-Some' Paradox: stipulations for a new D-feature
[+R]
The following stipulation attempts to locate the precise D-feature
involved in restricting a certain class of Determiners from interacting
with a Non-count Noun complement. As was sketched out above, and
eluding to in the brief discussion herein on Feature Theory, we
believe that the only viable D-feature available to do the job would
be a potential Referential Feature on D, labeled here as an [+R]-feature.
This [+R]-feature was brought to light above as being one deciding
feature, sensitive to number, which could signal the Non-count Noun
acceptability. We saw this feature in opposition to the [Q]-feature.
In accordance to this newly created stipulation on D-features, the
bundle of Determiner sub-categorization could be viewed as having
the following elements. (This is by no means an exhaustive list):
(12)
Determiner Features => |
(i) [+/-Nominative], [+/-Def], [+/-Pl],
etc., etc. and |
|
(ii) [+/-R] vs. [+/-Q]:
(iii) [Q] -Interpretable (=Existential, +Polarity)
(iv) [Q] +Interpretable (=Universal, -Polarity) |
Although we might initially be led into considering all semantically-based
[R]s as having at least some property associated with -Intrep(retability)-so
as to account for the acceptable modification of Non-count Nouns-we
find that such modification is achieved only via a default measure.
We conclude that all [R] Determiners are +Interp and have semantic
material. We further conclude that only certain first order gradients
of [Q] share this +Interp property, other second order grades contain
an additional formal feature and are therefore labeled as having
the following [+Q, -Interp] properties. Since we conclude that Non-count
Nouns have some quasi-formal [-Interp] property perhaps linked to
AGR(eement) and/or INFL(ection)-e.g., regarding how their number
specificity interacts with the determiner-only [-Interp] Existential
Determiners can abide by the affective constituent conditions placed
on Non-count nouns.
At closer look, the story here gets convoluted. The question is
as follows: Why should it be that substantive [+Interp] R-Determiners
may modify formal [-Interp] Non-count Nouns, but not [+Interp] Q-Determiners?
We attempt to sort this out below.
In addition to such finer-grained distinctions placed upon Determiners,
Chomsky has also come clean and further suggested that certain features
(such as D-features) may be either Interpretable [+Interp], or Uninterpretable
[-Interp] to semantic conditions having to do with logical form
(LF)) (1995: 278). Chomsky labels such semantically based features
as (phi) f-features.
As a further classification, it is not too unlikely that [R] features
do contain [+INTERP] semantic material, whereas [Q] features don't.
At this level, we could tentatively conclude that what drives the
acceptability factor in determining whether Determiners can work
with apparent Non-count Nouns is thus the dual distinction of [+R],
and [+INTERP]. The claim that these two features apparently hold
a default status towards Non-count nouns helps to extent the role
of features beyond the mere lexical-categorial level and into the
scope of syntax proper
6. Summary
Let's pause here and examine what has been said thus far. It seems
that any attempt to capture this unique and sensitive distribution
of determiners to Non-count Nouns, we need to split [Q] Determiners
into two sub-classes: +/-Interp. The best scenario here is that
the nature behind this sub-division is somehow associated with a
particular formal feature having to do specifically with Agr(eement),
or more general with notions of INFL(ection): e.g., Partitive
case/agreement (=Existential, [-INTERP]) vs. Universal
default case/agreement (=generic, [+INTERP]) might come to
mind first. (E.g., Partitive determiners might be used in this case
to modify mass nouns in order to indicate that the noun refers to
only a part of a whole, cf. some furniture). In sum, it
is suggested above that only one class of [Q] determiners with relevant
Agr/Infl conditions can modify Non-count Nouns, while the second
[Q] determiner cannot. One way to approach this split is by looking
into finer subcategorial analyses of semantic features (per
se). Semantic features are crucial for proper LF interpretability;
hence they are stated as being [+Interp(retable)]. Other more formal
features not needed for LF representation are thus [-Interp(retable)].
Stipulation 1: What
we are suggesting is that there is one branch of [Q-Det] which
is marked for [+INTERP] and that such determiners needn't necessarily
check-off features. For this reason, these determiners cannot
modify more formal [-]count nouns since such nouns do have formal
features which require checking-off. This formal non-count feature
seems to correspond to an Existential Partitive Case and or
Agreement-thus, [-]count nouns need appropriate Q-Dets which
contain this formal [-INTERP] feature so as to motivate proper
checking.
Stipulation 2: What
we are suggesting is a number sensitivity to feature relation:
(a) [-]Count (+FORMAL) number sensitivity)=> Existential [-INTERP]
adaptation,
(b) [+]Count (-FORMAL) no number sensitivity)=>Universal [+INTERP]
adaptation.
Thus, Non-count nouns place a sort of Agr/Infl condition, while
Count nouns place no such condition (as it relates to its semantic
reference). In sum, a split Q-feature distributions looks like the
following:
(a) Q: f-nominal
Features => +Interp [Number, Person, etc. & Universal Q]
(b) Q: Case/Agr-Features => -Interp [+/-Nominative, Partitive,
& Existential Q]
The number sensitivity that contains referential material is thus
Universal, while the number sensitivity feature, which is agreement
driven, is Existential. Only those determiners that carry this [-INTERP]
on the number feature can enter into a checking relation and modify
non-count nouns
7. Minimalist Optimality: A Formal N-Feature?
Economy We
assume that this added formal feature attached to Q [-Interp], for
reasons having to do with the affective expression of Partitive
Case and/or INFL, like all formal features, must delete (via checking)
before arriving at LF. A minimalistic treatment toward this checking
configuration would be to stipulate that a corresponding Det with
similar case features must enter into that same checking relation.
If, say, a [+INTERP] Det. were to enter into such a checking relation,
its +Interp feature would nevertheless remain undeleted, calling
into question the totality of the checking environment. Conditions
stemming from MP assumptions would rather stipulate that the totality
of the checking relation be optimal, placing strict conditions on
Spec-Head configurations. Such conditions would satisfy considerations
placed on Economy. Without these conditions, while a [+INTERP
[Q-D]] Determiner could theoretically check such nouns, its D-feature
would not be deleted. A much more optimal account would be to stipulate
for a [-INTERP [Q-D]] Determiner to enter into the checking arrangement-this
would ensure that both formal D and N f-features would delete. (This
would in any event prevent superfluous steps in derivation, both
D & N are checked within the same checking domain simultaneously).
This notion that Non-count nouns have a formal case [-INTERP] would
likewise predict that child English stage-1 language acquisition
would be exempt from such mass noun expressions, and words such
as furniture might be rather treated as a count noun by
default: e.g., Me have two furnitures, etc., etc..
8. Restating Features: Lexical-D, Functional-N
The twin checkers of Determiner & Noun are indeed exceptional
in this situation since Nouns are traditionally categorized as a
lexical (non-formal) categories void of any formal features that
would require checking. It is our view that Non-count Nouns must
be considered as an aspect of a functional DP. In other words, they
are functional categories. Similar treatments which sought to strip
down an otherwise categorial D(P) replete of its functional features
rendering the Determiner category more-or-less a 'nominal-like'
default in nature has been suggested in the literature (see Galasso
1999). A claim could be made that certain Determiners (presumably
acting as defaults) may be void of any real formal features (particularly
having to do with case) and hence take-on Objective default settings.
Chomsky (1995: 288) discusses the possibility that a DP could, in
theory, be void of formal case if its associate likewise bears this
out. This is evident in the early stages of child English. For example,
consider the following stage-1 utterance: the sentence [VP
Me want [DP [-Interp] the/a car]] contains
no evidence of functional projections (cf. Radford 1990). Yet, a
DP here indeed projects, albeit without its fully- fledged set of
formal features. Meisel (1990, 1995) has likewise suggested that
(seemingly default) DPs associated with a lexical VP lower down
in the syntactic tree may not contain the full array of functional
material otherwise attributed to that same DP as associated with
the higher INFL. For instance, in the sentence [IP The boys
like [DP the ball]], only the first the in associated with
the functional category IP would contain all relevant functional
material. The second the may simply have a default status-say, regarding
case. In fact, Meisel attributes this default DP status to early
language mixing/switching between Determiners and Nouns that fall
below INFL (the second the), or among utterances that contain no
fully emerged INFL. He goes on to claim that it is only with the
full emergence of INFL that we find a DP worthy of its formal functional
status. In other words, at an early stage of language acquisition
(as well as with bilingual code-switching), a DP may be void of
certain formal features-features of which are then said to be linked
to the maturation of an associative functional category IP. In an
ironic twist of faiths, it turns out that what we have striped and
pruned away in functional features, from the otherwise formal Determiner
leaving a category DP shell intact with only lexical default features,
we have conversely furnished to the Noun, playing havoc with what
one traditional understood as a Lexical-Noun vs. Functional-Determiner
categorial distinctions and labels. A case in point: it seems that
this newly clad Noun, replete with at least one formal feature now
in its repertoire may out-rank the deprived Determiner of its class.
As stated above, categories, lexical vs. functional have now taken
the back seat to feature distributions, and features can find themselves
in an array of combinatory environments, a predicament that would
have been theoretically inconceivable before the demise of the 'categorial
label' DP, VP, etc. brought on by MP.
Returning to Chomsky's suggestion cited just above (op.cit: 288),
reflect on the dualist of Expletives It and There.
(The former takes f and case features while the latter lacks f and
case). It may be that both determiners enter into a formal Head-Complement
checking relationship in order to erase relevant features such as
Agr (viz., There is/are...vs. It is/*are); however, there
would be no [-INTERP] features on the 'pure expletive' there
in need of checking. This duality is somewhat analogous to the distinction
we are making with count vs. non-count nouns. It may be that the
same feature [-INTERP] found in the Expletive It, though
not in There, may be associated with the [-INTERP] feature
found in Non-Count Nouns: namely, the Exist(ential) Feature, recalling
that expletives may take proper case via association with the adjacent
noun.
Consider the optimal twin-checking domain below:

What the tree above shows is that the Non-count Noun lexical item
furniture contains the [-Interp] Head features of [-COUNT] &
[Q-Exist] along with the default [R]-hence, a formal Functional
Phrase must project from out of the Noun. Sentence (e-g) crash because
the formal Non-count N-feature doesn't have a compatible D-feature
in which to erase the relevant features, while sentence (a-d) are
compatible with feature easing: viz., Q-Exist instigates checking
whereas Q-Univ doesn't In one sense, we could say that Non-count
Nouns in fact do contain strong features-the type of formal feature
that, for example, has been reserved for only Inflectional verbs
(T/Agr) and Case marked Nouns and Pronouns (Partitive, Nominative,
Accusative, Genitive). It is clear, however, that proto-typical
lexical nouns and verbs don't have strong features. Keeping in agreement
with MP, we must say that non-count nouns are somewhat similar to
Pronouns (which fall under DP) only in the strict sense that its
agreement properties seem to be of a functional nature-all other
lexical vs. functional distinctions pertaining to nouns and verbs
hold.
9. Summary and Conclusion
In summary, we believe Non-count Nouns can be characterized in
terms of a semantic feature (+/-Count /+/-Individuatability) which
effects a particular distributional phenomenon regarding what
kinds of determiners will be allowed to act as a modifier. This
distributional phenomenon share a common link to formal verbs-hence,
we come to attribute Non-count nouns with having a formal feature
similar to INFL-related verbs (found projecting under IP). For
this reason, we conclude that Non-count Nouns should be considered
as a quasi-functional projection, labeled above as projecting
/ extending an FP from out of the noun (as shown in (13) above).
In sum, the distributions of Non-count Nouns to their Determiner
counterparts are arranged as follows:
1. We conclude that all [R] Referential determiners-e.g., the/this/that/those/my/our
etc. are to be considered as having a semantically rich [+Interp]
D-feature (and contain no polarity association) and hence may
only as a default measure, in connection to referentiality, come
to modify Non-count Nouns. (They don't instigate any formal checking).
Though [R] determiners these/those are equally considered
as [+Interp] for referentiality, they are nonetheless banned from
Non-count Noun modification due to their exclusive Plural Agreement
markings, as shown in opposition to their singular counterparts
this/that (respectively), being that non-count nouns
are inherently singular). (If it were the case that non-count
nouns be inherently plural, the opposite distribution would have
taken course).
2. Q-Universal Determiners a/one/a-couple-of/a-few/many/several/every
etc. can't modify Non-count Nouns because they are (i)
theoretically considered to hold [+Inter] features and therefore
don't instigate checking, and are (ii) as opposed to
[R] determiner, not to be considered as holding a default status.
Given that their counter-part [-Interp] Q gradients step-in to
fulfill the requirements put on checking, in an economical manner,
Universal determiners don't have [-Inter] formal capacity and
thus are excluded from engaging in a formal checking relation.
As a final verdict, we believe that the basic mechanism behind
the so named 'Any-Some' paradox, as spawn by an affective
constituency factor, can similarly account for what we see regarding
the number sensitivity found with Non-count Nouns. Furthermore,
we suggest that a formal polarity feature which is attributed to
[-INTERP] & [Q-D] determinacy was behind this number sensitivity.
As we saw in (§4), Polarity items must contain a separate feature
that restricts the item from occurring in only those structures
that contain the 'affective' construct. We conclude that a similar
affective feature may also be behind what we find regarding the
restrictiveness of D+N configuration among Non-count Nouns. What
this suggests is that Non-count Nouns should perhaps be thought
of more-or-less along the same lines as a Functional category in
view that they share with their Determiner counterpart at least
one specific formal features. The notion that categories such as
Nouns and Determiners no longer can be simply labeled as Lexical
vs. Functional (respectively) and that the item's features have
more of a say regarding how one should interpret the item syntactically
goes to the heart of what Chomsky believes to be the cornerstone
to syntactic theory within the Minimalist Program.
<<
Back to Index
References Chomsky, N. (1994) 'Bare Phrase Structure'.
MIT occasional papers in linguistics 5.
Chomsky, N. (1995) The Minimalist Program. MIT Press.
Clahsen, H. (1994) 'Underspecification and lexical learning in early
child grammars'. Essex Research Reports in Linguistics
4. University of Essex, U.K.
Galasso, J. (1999) The Acquisition of Functional Categories:
A Case Study. unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation. University
of Essex, U.K.
Klima, E. (1964) 'Negation in English'. In J.A. Fodor & J.J.Katz
(eds) The Structure of Language, pp. 246-323. Prentice
Hall, N.J.
Koppe, R. & Meisel, J. (1995) 'Code-switching in bilingual first
language acquisition'. In Milroy, L. & Muysken, P.
(eds) One speaker, two languages. Cambridge University
Press.
Lenneberg, E. (1975) 'The concept of language Differentiation'.
In Foundations of Language Development. vol.1. Lenneberg,
E. & Lenneberg, E. (eds). The UNESCO Press: Paris
Meisel, J. (1990) INFL-ection: subject-verb agreement. In J. Meisel
(ed) Two first languages: Early grammatical development
in bilingual children. Foris: Dordrecht.
Myers-Scotton,C. (1995) 'A lexically based model for code-switching'.
In One speaker, two languages. Milroy, L.
& Muysken, P. (eds) Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, U.K.
O'Grady, W. (1999) 'The acquisition of syntactic representations:
a general nativist approach'. In Handbook of Child
Language Acquisition. Ritchie, W. & Bhatia, T. (eds). Academic
Press
Radford, A. (1990) Syntactic Theory and the Acquisition of English
Syntax. Blackwell Press: Oxford.
---(1997)
Syntactic Theory and the Structure of English. Cambridge
University Press: Cambridge.
NOTES:
[1] Chomsky (1965) suggested early on that a binary feature
specification could work with regards to phonology—for example,
between [+ Nasal], and [+ Plosive].
[2] . See also work currenlty being done on ‘Underspecification
of Feature Theory’ by Wexler (1994), Hoekstra & Hyams (1998),
Radford & Galasso (1998) (among others).
[3] We follow Abney (1986, 1987) concerning the analysis
of DP.
[4] Lenneberg (ed) (1975) The concept of langauge differention.
In Foundations of Language Development. Vol.1. (pp.17-33).
|